It was regular practice in the medieval university for faculty and students to engage in the art of disputation. This blog presupposes the corporate nature of the theological enterprise, supposing that theology, particularly Lutheran theology, can once again clarify its truth claims and provide rational justification for its positions.
Saturday, June 09, 2012
Acting in Conformity with the Law versus Acting From or Because of the Law
When Lutherans come to think about God's Law, they sometimes think and say some rather confusing things. Oftentimes this confusion reigns because they don't properly distinguish from among the nature of law, its motivation and its effects.
Properly speaking, the law is that which ought to be the case, as it is commanded and enforced by a proper authority: God. While the law is not a description of what actually happens, it is the real reality of what should happen: That which ought to be is as that which ought to be. Accordingly, Lutherans should be nomological realists; they should hold that the law is something objectively present outside of human awareness, perception, conception and language. Thinking of such a law is, however, prone to abstraction.
Over the last centuries, Lutherans have been busy trying to follow Luther's lead in not thinking about the law abstractly, but rather considering it concretely. Accordingly, the law is not simply an eternal set of prescriptions, but is itself a power. The law, in fact, accuses. It kills.
But the question arises: In what sense can the law accuse and kill? Even asking this question seems misguided to Lutheran insiders. How could a Lutheran theologian seriously suggest that he knows not the sense in which the law accuses and kills? Does he not get even the basics of Lutheran theology?
Seemingly straightforward questions that somehow get asked anyway generally suggest that there has been some adjustment in the underlying set of assumptions or paradigm. If one starts with the reality of human existence and the human Urerlebnis of being held fully responsible for not being able to do what one ought (Elert), then indeed asking in what sense the law accuses and kills is like asking in what sense water is wet. However, if one is serious about theological realism, then things change a bit. The law gains an ontological vitality not entailed by its phenomenological contour. Now the law is because God is. The law becomes an expression of what God is in and through creation. A divine nomological ontology now sharply distinguishes the law in se from its effects pro nobis, and from our own motivations to do the law.
Kant famously distinguished acting because of or from duty from merely acting in accordance with duty. For Kant, the motivation for doing an action is what is at issue morally. I can save the old lady about to be hit by the truck for a number of reasons, some quite selfish or misguided. (Maybe I don't like to see the hoods of trucks dented or dirtied.) To act solely on the basis that saving her is the right thing to do is to act morally for the right reason. (Kant used the example of the shopkeeper who acted merely in accordance with duty - - and not from duty - - in not duping his customer because the shopkeeper wants to build a good reputation and a better business.)
The distinction between acting in accordance with a rule or acting from, because or due to a rule is helpful, I think, in getting clear on how the law accuses and kills.
God wills x but Bob cannot seemingly or easily do x. This willing of x by God is real: it exists apart from human awareness, perception, conception and language. Now Bob can live "according to the law" by so acting with respect to x because of, from or due to x. Such life under the law is itself a fundamental existential response to the reality of the law. One can attempt to be moral and do what it is that one ought to do out of proper motivation: One acts solely because this action is commanded by God. While acting from the law is good for Kant, it is bad for Luther (and all of us generally) because to act because of the law is to prioritize, reify, and focus upon the fact of x. Such prioritizing, reifying and focusing upon x can only push one further away from the author of x.
Fortunately, what is bad of Kant is good for Luther (and all of us generally). While to act merely in accordance with duty is, for Kant, not really to be acting in a morally manifest way - -though he clearly says that such acting can be wholly appropriate - - acting in accordance with the law can be for Christians a highly laudable state. (One should act so that one's right-hand does not know what one's left-hand is doing.) Grace is eschewing a life lived "according to the law" so that one can "act in accordance with the law" and not due to the law. Acting merely in accordance with the law is what grace accomplishes. The law is taken up, not abolished. What is abolished is acting from the law; what remains is acting in accordance with the law from proper inclination (spontaneous thankfulness) and not from the demands of the law itself. Such an acting is neither accusatory nor nefarious; it simply is on the basis of He who is.
If we keep with the central story of Christianity - - there is a God and this God has a definite intentionality for His creation - - then the Lutheran focus on Law and Gospel is properly understood as a pertaining not primarily to the order of things, but mainly to the order of the human heart with respect to things. (I am not wholly denying here that nature is out of conformity with the law under the conditions of the Fall, but simply not thematizing it here.) Is the primal ought manifest to human beings as accusation or gift? Is it finally that which kills or that which makes alive? It all goes back to the motivation of the human heart, and with respect to the importance of motivation Kant was fully in accord with Luther. What is different is the nature of motivation. Luther knew what Paul proclaimed: To act due to the law was to live according to the flesh. But to be gifted to act freely merely in accordance with the law is the most blessed life available to all; it is to live in the dynamics of the Spirit.
Monday, June 04, 2012
Why Meaning Matters
A number of years ago when the MacNiel/Lehrer Report still appeared on PBS, there was an economist who answered a particular question using some of the technical language of his discipline. The response from the other guest was instructive. Listening to what the economist had offered, he remonstrated, "Why, that's just theological."
The economist had clearly taken a heavy hit. Calling his language theological in that context was to suggest a number of things: 1) His language was not clear, 2) His language was ambiguous, 3) His language made only dubious claims to truth, 4) His language was needlessly complex, 5) His language was useless.
I have from the beginning of my time in theology sought a particular precision. The reason for this is simply that very early on I learned how captivating theological language could be. It seemed to me that one could enter another world by using such language. When I was young it was great fun to read theology, to envision new possibilities, and to address theological problems. But something happened to me on my way to a Ph. D.
I began to realize that everything I was thinking when I was thinking theologically was comprised of propositions comprised of terms and predications of identity and attribution. I began to think that if what I was thinking was to be true, I must get very clear on what it was precisely that I was thinking so I knew what it precisely was that was to be true. This meant that I must analyze the language of my theological thinking to see what precisely it meant.
But when I began to explore what it is precisely that theological language meant, I ran up against a host of problems. Though I could use theological language correctly, - - I could use it in such ways that fit the linguistic situation (one might say, I could satisfy the appropriate stimulus/response conditionals theologically) - - I did not know exactly how my theological language related to other kinds of discourse. When talking to people who did not know how to employ theological language like I thought I then did, I started to realize that I did not always know how to translate what I was saying theologically into types of language that they grasped, language that related to the world in which both they and I lived. In this way, I began to worry about what precise claims I was making theologically and whether there was evidence to support those claims I was making.
Long ago I concluded that the more one likely agonizes over what precisely one means when doing theology, the less theology one is likely to do. Wonderful, learned and deeply evocative theology can be written without one knowing precisely what one means in the writing. This is, of course, to a degree true of all disciplines. Does one know the precise identity conditions of each term one uses in fundamental particle physics? While the answer to this is perhaps, "no," there is a difference. One has a public, objective semantic yardstick in fundamental particle physics that one does not possess in theology. This is why one can look up the precise meaning of a term in the first context but not the second. In theology, the meaning of terms and phrases depends deeply on who is employing them. In theology it is fundamentally meaning that matters.
The Institute of Lutheran Theology believes that it is critically important to grasp the semantic question in theology. We in the developed countries of the West live at a time in which great numbers of people are abandoing the use of theological language. The reason, in my opinion, is that far too many now think the language is not clear and unambiguous, that it makes dubious claims, and that is is complex and useless. For many people, in fact, the clearer the language becomes - - I am thinking now of some expressions of Evangelical theology - - the less likely many think it is to be true, and the more likely it is to be true, the less clear they believe it is. Somehow in theology, meaning and truth, the twin pillars of semantics, have become inversely proportional.
I have been posting this week about the Institute of Lutheran Theology. At ILT we are serious about studying theology seriously. This means, among other things, that not only God and his work in Jesus Christ is at issue for us, but also the meaning of God working in Jesus Christ. The reason meaning matters is that it is necessary for truth, and when the truth at issue is the Truth, then the meaning that matters is that which really matters.
The economist had clearly taken a heavy hit. Calling his language theological in that context was to suggest a number of things: 1) His language was not clear, 2) His language was ambiguous, 3) His language made only dubious claims to truth, 4) His language was needlessly complex, 5) His language was useless.
I have from the beginning of my time in theology sought a particular precision. The reason for this is simply that very early on I learned how captivating theological language could be. It seemed to me that one could enter another world by using such language. When I was young it was great fun to read theology, to envision new possibilities, and to address theological problems. But something happened to me on my way to a Ph. D.
I began to realize that everything I was thinking when I was thinking theologically was comprised of propositions comprised of terms and predications of identity and attribution. I began to think that if what I was thinking was to be true, I must get very clear on what it was precisely that I was thinking so I knew what it precisely was that was to be true. This meant that I must analyze the language of my theological thinking to see what precisely it meant.
But when I began to explore what it is precisely that theological language meant, I ran up against a host of problems. Though I could use theological language correctly, - - I could use it in such ways that fit the linguistic situation (one might say, I could satisfy the appropriate stimulus/response conditionals theologically) - - I did not know exactly how my theological language related to other kinds of discourse. When talking to people who did not know how to employ theological language like I thought I then did, I started to realize that I did not always know how to translate what I was saying theologically into types of language that they grasped, language that related to the world in which both they and I lived. In this way, I began to worry about what precise claims I was making theologically and whether there was evidence to support those claims I was making.
Long ago I concluded that the more one likely agonizes over what precisely one means when doing theology, the less theology one is likely to do. Wonderful, learned and deeply evocative theology can be written without one knowing precisely what one means in the writing. This is, of course, to a degree true of all disciplines. Does one know the precise identity conditions of each term one uses in fundamental particle physics? While the answer to this is perhaps, "no," there is a difference. One has a public, objective semantic yardstick in fundamental particle physics that one does not possess in theology. This is why one can look up the precise meaning of a term in the first context but not the second. In theology, the meaning of terms and phrases depends deeply on who is employing them. In theology it is fundamentally meaning that matters.
The Institute of Lutheran Theology believes that it is critically important to grasp the semantic question in theology. We in the developed countries of the West live at a time in which great numbers of people are abandoing the use of theological language. The reason, in my opinion, is that far too many now think the language is not clear and unambiguous, that it makes dubious claims, and that is is complex and useless. For many people, in fact, the clearer the language becomes - - I am thinking now of some expressions of Evangelical theology - - the less likely many think it is to be true, and the more likely it is to be true, the less clear they believe it is. Somehow in theology, meaning and truth, the twin pillars of semantics, have become inversely proportional.
I have been posting this week about the Institute of Lutheran Theology. At ILT we are serious about studying theology seriously. This means, among other things, that not only God and his work in Jesus Christ is at issue for us, but also the meaning of God working in Jesus Christ. The reason meaning matters is that it is necessary for truth, and when the truth at issue is the Truth, then the meaning that matters is that which really matters.
Thursday, May 31, 2012
The Institute of Lutheran Theology's Masters of Sacred Theology
Readers of this blog soon
realize that I have theological interests. This is why I continued to be
engaged in the building of the Institute of Lutheran Theology, a new Lutheran
School of Theology centered in Jesus Christ which profoundly engages questions
of theological truth as they relate to our contemporary intellectual and
cultural horizon.
Did you know that the
Institute of Lutheran Theology offers a Masters of Sacred Theology, the Sacrae
Theologiae Magister or STM? This post-M. Div. degree consists of
six graduate courses and a thesis (21 hours), and offers tracks in Reformation
Theology, Contemporary Lutheran Theology, and Issues in Science/Religion and
the Philosophy of Religion. The STM allows motivated students the
opportunity to pursue higher level coursework, either as a preparatory step for
study at the doctorate level or as a means of professional
development.
ILT is offering two
courses this fall in the STM program, a seminar in Pannenberg taught by Dr.
Paul Hinlicky and the required methodology course taught by me. Course
descriptions are as follows:
- HST 590: Contemporary Lutheran Dogmatics: Pannenberg's Systematic Theology: This seminar examines all three volumes of Wolfhart Pannenberg's systematic theology.
- EPR 580: Methodology and Approaches to Graduate Study: This required course introduces graduate students to the standard critical approaches and issues relevant to doing successful and informed work in historical theology, contemporary theology and the philosophy of religion. Students will read primary sources from both the continental and analytical traditions. Historical, phenomenological, existential, hermeneutical, analytical, social-scientific and post-structuralist approaches are examined.
Students
are expected to possess mastery of verbal and written English for course
participation and written work. There are no other specific language
requirements for the STM, but students researching particular areas will be
expected to have working knowledge of the languages needed to complete their
research. Depending upon the student’s interests and project, this may
include knowledge of Greek, Latin, German, French or another modern foreign
language. Because of the importance of primary text reading in the German
sources, ILT occasionally offers theological German as a benefit to its
students - - though the course does not count towards fulfilling the 21 hour
requirement for graduation.
- HST 585: Theological German. Students wanting to do research in German may take this course which introduces the theological vocabulary and successful techniques of reading theological German.
Students from all religious traditions are invited to
study. All courses are delivered in real time and on-line through our
video conferencing platform. All students see and interact with each
other and the professor. For more information about ILT programming,
please visit our website or call 605-692-9337. Students can still apply for
fall admission into the STM program. Our admission requirements are
listed below.
- Prior completion of an M.Div. degree, an M.A. in theology or closely related field of study, or a related degree demonstrating preparation for advanced theological work
- Completion of application form
- Three recommendations from individuals with knowledge of likely academic performance
- Official graduate and undergraduate transcripts must be sent directly to ILT
- (International applicants only) International applicants are required to submit a score on the Test of English as a Foreign Language (TOEFL). The score must be 550 or above, with an essayrating of at least 5.0, and cannot be more than one year old.
Tuesday, May 29, 2012
The Semantics of 'Jesus Christ'
Oftentimes we miss the things that are most obvious. This is true in all areas of life, and in theology especially. What is obvious, but not often enough clearly thought through, is the way in which the meaning of 'Jesus Christ' has changed in the past couple of centuries. There are vast differences in the way Bultmann and Irenaeus understand 'Jesus Christ', differences so vast that Irenaeus and Bultmann could best be said to understand 'Jesus Christ' in radically different ways. Unfortunately, theology has often failed to realize this and to address the fact and nature of the difference. In order to see this all more clearly, let us reflect upon an example from baseball.
A pitcher in a baseball game is someone who throws the ball past the batter. He would not be a pitcher if he were not to do this. The implicit rule is something like this, "If x is a baseball pitcher, then ceteris paribus x will occupy a position y feet from home plate, and x will attempt to throw the ball over home plate such that the batter will either not hit the ball on three hitable pitches, or hit the ball in the air such that it can be caught, or on the ground such that a throw can be made to first base prior to the batter reaching first base after hitting the ball."
Now I don't for a moment think this is a very accurate stating of the rule in question, but it should at least show what it is that I am thinking when I say that within the game of baseball, there are clear rules governing the role of pitcher. If I am talking about the rules governing actual pitchers and batters and actual games, I could be said to be speaking of the rules in the material mode. However, if I am talking about the way that the term 'pitcher' relates to other terms like 'hitter', 'catcher', 'innings', I could be said to be speaking of the rules in the formal mode.
One of the great advances of twentieth century philosophy was to see that much language we take to be in the material mode can be more deeply studied, and its nature clarified, if we interpret such language to be in the formal mode. The shift from talk in the material mode of objects and properties to the formal mode of terms and predicates is sometimes termed "semantic ascent." (For instance, we might cease talking about whether unicorns exist and began talking about whether the word 'unicorn' has any useful role to play in our theory.) While undertaking a semantic ascent in baseball may have negligible ontological significance, doing so with respect to pi mesons certainly does. How so?
If we are operating in the material mode and say that a pi meson is a hadron with bayron number of 0, we are declaring (probably) that for all x, x is a pi meson just in case x is a hadron with the bayron number of 0, and there is some such x. In the formal mode, and after taking proper semantic ascent, we claim merely that in our background meta-language the term 'pi meson' can be substituted salve veritate with the locution 'a hadron with the bayron number of 0' and that the term 'pi meson' has a useful role to play in our assumed fundamental particle theory.
I like to talk about simple semantic matters in the philosophy of science as a way into discussion within theology generally. Take the classic definition of Chalcedon on the two natures of Christ:
"We also teach that we apprehend this one and only Christ-Son, Lord, only-begotten — in two natures; and we do this without confusing the two natures, without transmuting one nature into the other, without dividing them into two separate categories, without contrasting them according to area or function. The distinctiveness of each nature is not nullified by the union. Instead, the "properties" of each nature are conserved and both natures concur in one "person" and in one reality [hypostasis]. They are not divided or cut into two persons, but are together the one and only and only-begotten Word [Logos], God, the Lord Jesus Christ."
Now one could regard this to be a class of statements in the object language making a batch of ontological statements about the person of Christ. According to this interpretation, we must hold that there are such things as 'natures' comprised of classes of properties that append to the person (hypostasis) of Christ. These natures are distinctive classes of properties that are famously neither confused, transmuted or divided, contrasted, but nonetheless somehow "united" in the one person. It has be notoriously difficult to try to clarify the ontological situation here.
But one could perform a semantic ascent and place such discourse into the formal mode. Now the Definition gets read as a specification of the rules by which one will use a particular language. It is permitted that the term 'human' and term 'divine' both be predicated of the name 'Jesus Christ' even though the term 'human nature' has a set of entailments normally not in the set of entailments from 'divine nature'. (One could perform this semantic ascent in myriad and sundry ways, so please excuse my clumsiness here.)
In the formal mode, the ontological commitments of material mode interpretation are jettisoned, and the issue devolves to one of proper application of rules. Can a coherent set of rules be specified which permits the correct Christological affirmations and disallows those termed heretical? If such rules can be specified, then we are in a position - - with much of the tradition actually - - to talk about a specific theological grammar. The issue has become one of syntax. How are the words of theological theory used?
Now I want to introduce another topic that will connect with what I have just said. Notice how differently one investigates the ontological and the soteriological? While a causal analysis is not entailed in the first, it is in the second. Take, for instance, a set of abstract (existing) objects and the relationships that hold between them. The set of all triples does exist and, for all I know, it may be identical with the number '3'. One can make ontological assertions about these objects and no causal connection between them - - or between them and me - - is presupposed. But notice how different it is to speak about Jesus Christ. Here the very logic of discourse about Christ presupposes a causal connection with humanity - - including me. Christ could not be Christ without there being a saving causal relationship with respect to me. (Or at least this was true up until quite recently in the theological tradition. Clearly a Tillichian could hold that the symbol of the Christ existentially empowers without saying that the symbol has in itself causal power. The symbol in itself could be causally inert, yet a particular subject could respond to it in a particular way. This would make the symbol an abstract object. This understanding of 'Christ' is, I would argue, quite different from that of the tradition.)
Now I wish to introduce a final topic. Philosophers of science routinely distinguish realist from nonrealist interpretations of scientific theory. A realist with respect to pi mesons would regard the material mode presentation of pi meson theory - - theory in the object language - - to be making ontological claims about the way that the world is apart from human awareness, perception, conception and language. An irrealist interpretation would note the way that the object language of the theory behaves and understands that this behavior could have explanatory and predictive power - - in terms of the ways the rules work - - but would nonetheless not want to claim that in the nature of the case the world has such objects, properties and causal relationships specified by the theories.
Finally we come to the point. The semantics of 'Jesus Christ' at the time of the Definition assumed a material mode reading which was thoroughly soteriological. As the tradition developed and, in particular, was transformed by the Enlightenment, this original material mode ontological interpretation was increasingly transformed to a formal mode interpretation. (This argument can be made, I think, though there are a great many prima facie objections to this generalization that must be met.) As we moved away from the nineteenth century and its penchant for various forms of reductionism in theology, we entered into a phase of twentieth century theology that would assume - - whether it said so or not - - a regnant formal mode interpretation of theological language. What was important was the regular ways in which theological language was employed and the use to which it was put, not the ontology associated with a classical understanding of that language. (How else could metaphysics become disassociated from theology?) Theological irrealism could be made completely consistent with the correct use of theological language. As Wittgenstein trenchantly remarked, "What is important here is that the language-game is played."
The thing that is closest to Lutheran theology is the meaning of 'Jesus is the Christ'. It is this meaning, I argue, that has been fundamentally changed over the past centuries. Though the language-game continues to be played, and the rules can remain in principle specifiable, an unnoticed move to the formal mode has in reality happened. That this has happened is evidenced by how ontology has become divorced from eschatology. Eschatological/soteriological interpretations of theological language that are confidently assumed to not be ontological clearly evidence that the previous material mode interpretation of theological language has become in actuality a formal mode interpretation. No longer even is it deemed theologically central that theological realism hold, a realism that would have seemed necessary to the tradition if one were to have any real soteriology.
What has happened on our watch is that we have allowed the language of theology to remain formally correct while we have come to deem it relevant that it in fact refers! But clearly in the theological tradition reference was central to the question of the semantics of theological language. Unlike irrealist interpretations of scientific theory, realism in theology becomes necessary to hold the semantics of theological language consistent with the theological tradition.
A pitcher in a baseball game is someone who throws the ball past the batter. He would not be a pitcher if he were not to do this. The implicit rule is something like this, "If x is a baseball pitcher, then ceteris paribus x will occupy a position y feet from home plate, and x will attempt to throw the ball over home plate such that the batter will either not hit the ball on three hitable pitches, or hit the ball in the air such that it can be caught, or on the ground such that a throw can be made to first base prior to the batter reaching first base after hitting the ball."
Now I don't for a moment think this is a very accurate stating of the rule in question, but it should at least show what it is that I am thinking when I say that within the game of baseball, there are clear rules governing the role of pitcher. If I am talking about the rules governing actual pitchers and batters and actual games, I could be said to be speaking of the rules in the material mode. However, if I am talking about the way that the term 'pitcher' relates to other terms like 'hitter', 'catcher', 'innings', I could be said to be speaking of the rules in the formal mode.
One of the great advances of twentieth century philosophy was to see that much language we take to be in the material mode can be more deeply studied, and its nature clarified, if we interpret such language to be in the formal mode. The shift from talk in the material mode of objects and properties to the formal mode of terms and predicates is sometimes termed "semantic ascent." (For instance, we might cease talking about whether unicorns exist and began talking about whether the word 'unicorn' has any useful role to play in our theory.) While undertaking a semantic ascent in baseball may have negligible ontological significance, doing so with respect to pi mesons certainly does. How so?
If we are operating in the material mode and say that a pi meson is a hadron with bayron number of 0, we are declaring (probably) that for all x, x is a pi meson just in case x is a hadron with the bayron number of 0, and there is some such x. In the formal mode, and after taking proper semantic ascent, we claim merely that in our background meta-language the term 'pi meson' can be substituted salve veritate with the locution 'a hadron with the bayron number of 0' and that the term 'pi meson' has a useful role to play in our assumed fundamental particle theory.
I like to talk about simple semantic matters in the philosophy of science as a way into discussion within theology generally. Take the classic definition of Chalcedon on the two natures of Christ:
"We also teach that we apprehend this one and only Christ-Son, Lord, only-begotten — in two natures; and we do this without confusing the two natures, without transmuting one nature into the other, without dividing them into two separate categories, without contrasting them according to area or function. The distinctiveness of each nature is not nullified by the union. Instead, the "properties" of each nature are conserved and both natures concur in one "person" and in one reality [hypostasis]. They are not divided or cut into two persons, but are together the one and only and only-begotten Word [Logos], God, the Lord Jesus Christ."
Now one could regard this to be a class of statements in the object language making a batch of ontological statements about the person of Christ. According to this interpretation, we must hold that there are such things as 'natures' comprised of classes of properties that append to the person (hypostasis) of Christ. These natures are distinctive classes of properties that are famously neither confused, transmuted or divided, contrasted, but nonetheless somehow "united" in the one person. It has be notoriously difficult to try to clarify the ontological situation here.
But one could perform a semantic ascent and place such discourse into the formal mode. Now the Definition gets read as a specification of the rules by which one will use a particular language. It is permitted that the term 'human' and term 'divine' both be predicated of the name 'Jesus Christ' even though the term 'human nature' has a set of entailments normally not in the set of entailments from 'divine nature'. (One could perform this semantic ascent in myriad and sundry ways, so please excuse my clumsiness here.)
In the formal mode, the ontological commitments of material mode interpretation are jettisoned, and the issue devolves to one of proper application of rules. Can a coherent set of rules be specified which permits the correct Christological affirmations and disallows those termed heretical? If such rules can be specified, then we are in a position - - with much of the tradition actually - - to talk about a specific theological grammar. The issue has become one of syntax. How are the words of theological theory used?
Now I want to introduce another topic that will connect with what I have just said. Notice how differently one investigates the ontological and the soteriological? While a causal analysis is not entailed in the first, it is in the second. Take, for instance, a set of abstract (existing) objects and the relationships that hold between them. The set of all triples does exist and, for all I know, it may be identical with the number '3'. One can make ontological assertions about these objects and no causal connection between them - - or between them and me - - is presupposed. But notice how different it is to speak about Jesus Christ. Here the very logic of discourse about Christ presupposes a causal connection with humanity - - including me. Christ could not be Christ without there being a saving causal relationship with respect to me. (Or at least this was true up until quite recently in the theological tradition. Clearly a Tillichian could hold that the symbol of the Christ existentially empowers without saying that the symbol has in itself causal power. The symbol in itself could be causally inert, yet a particular subject could respond to it in a particular way. This would make the symbol an abstract object. This understanding of 'Christ' is, I would argue, quite different from that of the tradition.)
Now I wish to introduce a final topic. Philosophers of science routinely distinguish realist from nonrealist interpretations of scientific theory. A realist with respect to pi mesons would regard the material mode presentation of pi meson theory - - theory in the object language - - to be making ontological claims about the way that the world is apart from human awareness, perception, conception and language. An irrealist interpretation would note the way that the object language of the theory behaves and understands that this behavior could have explanatory and predictive power - - in terms of the ways the rules work - - but would nonetheless not want to claim that in the nature of the case the world has such objects, properties and causal relationships specified by the theories.
Finally we come to the point. The semantics of 'Jesus Christ' at the time of the Definition assumed a material mode reading which was thoroughly soteriological. As the tradition developed and, in particular, was transformed by the Enlightenment, this original material mode ontological interpretation was increasingly transformed to a formal mode interpretation. (This argument can be made, I think, though there are a great many prima facie objections to this generalization that must be met.) As we moved away from the nineteenth century and its penchant for various forms of reductionism in theology, we entered into a phase of twentieth century theology that would assume - - whether it said so or not - - a regnant formal mode interpretation of theological language. What was important was the regular ways in which theological language was employed and the use to which it was put, not the ontology associated with a classical understanding of that language. (How else could metaphysics become disassociated from theology?) Theological irrealism could be made completely consistent with the correct use of theological language. As Wittgenstein trenchantly remarked, "What is important here is that the language-game is played."
The thing that is closest to Lutheran theology is the meaning of 'Jesus is the Christ'. It is this meaning, I argue, that has been fundamentally changed over the past centuries. Though the language-game continues to be played, and the rules can remain in principle specifiable, an unnoticed move to the formal mode has in reality happened. That this has happened is evidenced by how ontology has become divorced from eschatology. Eschatological/soteriological interpretations of theological language that are confidently assumed to not be ontological clearly evidence that the previous material mode interpretation of theological language has become in actuality a formal mode interpretation. No longer even is it deemed theologically central that theological realism hold, a realism that would have seemed necessary to the tradition if one were to have any real soteriology.
What has happened on our watch is that we have allowed the language of theology to remain formally correct while we have come to deem it relevant that it in fact refers! But clearly in the theological tradition reference was central to the question of the semantics of theological language. Unlike irrealist interpretations of scientific theory, realism in theology becomes necessary to hold the semantics of theological language consistent with the theological tradition.
Labels:
Lutheran Theology,
philosophy of language,
semantics
Sunday, May 27, 2012
An Interpretive Center
People sometimes remark that I oftentimes seem to write about putative philosophical issues rather then staying directly on task and use the theological language of our great Lutheran tradition. Why would this be? Is it that I somehow am not interested deeply in the traditional objects of Lutheran theological reflection?
No, this is not true. I believe that the center of Lutheran theology is the proclamation of the free grace of Jesus Christ appropriated in faith. When serving in the parish, I preached this each and every week. I believe that the external Word interprets itself, striking the human heart both as Law and Gospel, and that through this Word we are justified and made free lords before God and dutiful servants to one another. I believe that the great ecumenical creeds of the Church make definite truth-claims, and I routinely confess their truth. I believe that Jesus Christ was true God and true man, and believe in Lutheran fashion in the genus maiestaticum, as well as the genus idiomaticum and genus apotelesmaticum. So why talk about all of the philosophical issues if this theological core of beliefs is at the center of things?
The reason I am interested in discussing philosophical issues (mostly semantic and ontological) is because while Lutherans can still say all of the right things, they don't necessarily mean by these things what Lutherans once meant.
But why should this be a problem if all the same things are confessed? Surely there can be different philosophischen Rictungen among confessing Lutherans. After all, did not Wilhelm Hermann famously argue that metaphysics (and its variations) are irrelevant to solid, Lutheran confessional theology? Did not the young Luther scholar Wilhelm Link, (who died much too soon in the war) argue that Luther claimed the same thing? Isn't the greatness of Lutheran theology found in the freedom of interpretation in one's confessions? Surely, we ought not to confuse the left hand and the right hand of God, the hand of reason, law and philosophy, and the hand of faith, grace and theology!
Luther in his various disputations would occasionally quip that what was finally important in disputing was an agreement not merely in speech, but in the things (in res). An agreement as to what is held or asserted has been crucially important in the development of doctrine generally and within the Lutheran Confessions specifically. The question is this: How does this Lutheran commitment to the truth of propositions from the tradition and the Confessions get appropriated in our time? My considered opinion is that there is a great deal of confusion here, and my fear is that this confusion could be disastrous for the future of Lutheran theology.
When one plays baseball, one plays by baseball rules. There are three outs per side, both teams batting once constitutes an inning, and there are nine innings in a game. (I am thinking about the major and minor leagues with respect to this last point.) Proper theological language has rules as well. One must know how to use the word 'Father' and the word 'Son'. Specifically, one must be able to say 'The Son is God', 'The Father is God', without saying 'The Father is the Son'. Rules permitting the right expressions in the right linguistic circumstances and prohibiting the wrong ones in the wrong circumstances are notoriously difficult to formulate, but there is little doubt that there exist some set of rules that undergird the modus loquendi theologicus.
So far so good. One could in principle formulate a theological game as well as a game of black hole theory. Within contemporary cosmological theory, certain terms occur in particular statements and not within others. Prima facie there does not seem to be much different between the formal structure of a Trinitarian language and that language of any heavily theoretical discipline. There is a proper and improper way of using terms and phrases. The question now confronts us: Are the semantics of the two games the same?
On this there is much difference of opinion, of course. Many would say that there is extra-linguistic set of referents to which the language of black holes is anchored that is not available for the theoretical language of the Trinity. But why would this be so? Why would one think there is some res that black hole theory has the theology does not have? One would not think this - - unless one had previous opinions about what is possible ontologically for the Trinity over and against black holes.
Since the time of the Enlightenment, there has been an increasing sense in the former Christian West that the language of theology does not make truth claims. While most within popular culture - - I am not talking here about philosophers of science - - would claim that there are clear truth conditions for black hole theory, they would not, if they reflected some, claim easily that there are similar truth conditions in theology. The reason, of course, is that for tens of millions of people theological language simply can't be making truth claims because such language is an expression of individual and cultural value. There simply is no realm of theological facts such that the rules of theological language can govern a linguistic usage that can bring the language into contact with a domain of extra-linguistic referents. The fact/value distinction is wholly enshrined within contemporary culture, and this descendent from the Enlightenment must be dealt with before theological language is afforded the same opportunity to refer as the language of black holes.
My claim has been and continues to be that the interpretive center has been lost within much of Lutheran theology in the first part of the twenty-first century. The problem has been that a general cultural/intellectual commitment to the Enlightenment paradigm, especially Kant, has led millions to presuppose different semantic possibilities for that language than that which generally characterized the tradition. I am not saying that much of this is explicit. (Increasingly few people even know the name 'Kant'.) But middle school children learn that science is about facts and religion is about values. They don't know the torturous intellectual history that brought civilization to this "insight." They are taught this fact/value distinction as if it fell from the heavens. It is part of the Enlightenment paradigm, a paradigm that functions as the default ontological posit of our time. What I am saying is this: To continue to divorce theology and metaphysics and to allow the fact/value distinction to stand inviolate, is to allow theological language not to be about truth, and it is thus to allow theological language to assume a different semantics than it previously had.
The Institute of Lutheran Theology is grounded in Scripture and Confessions. It holds assiduously to classical confessional Lutheran theology. Professors at ILT are passionate about their commitment to Scriptural truth and authority as it is known and understood through the hermeneutical lens of the Confessions. While students are exposed to the great Biblical exegetes and the great theologians of the tradition, they learn the most important thing, I believe, that a school of theology can impart: ILT believes that it is true that God was in Jesus Christ reconciling the world unto Himself, and that because of this truth we have good grounds to preach and teach in His Name.
No, this is not true. I believe that the center of Lutheran theology is the proclamation of the free grace of Jesus Christ appropriated in faith. When serving in the parish, I preached this each and every week. I believe that the external Word interprets itself, striking the human heart both as Law and Gospel, and that through this Word we are justified and made free lords before God and dutiful servants to one another. I believe that the great ecumenical creeds of the Church make definite truth-claims, and I routinely confess their truth. I believe that Jesus Christ was true God and true man, and believe in Lutheran fashion in the genus maiestaticum, as well as the genus idiomaticum and genus apotelesmaticum. So why talk about all of the philosophical issues if this theological core of beliefs is at the center of things?
The reason I am interested in discussing philosophical issues (mostly semantic and ontological) is because while Lutherans can still say all of the right things, they don't necessarily mean by these things what Lutherans once meant.
But why should this be a problem if all the same things are confessed? Surely there can be different philosophischen Rictungen among confessing Lutherans. After all, did not Wilhelm Hermann famously argue that metaphysics (and its variations) are irrelevant to solid, Lutheran confessional theology? Did not the young Luther scholar Wilhelm Link, (who died much too soon in the war) argue that Luther claimed the same thing? Isn't the greatness of Lutheran theology found in the freedom of interpretation in one's confessions? Surely, we ought not to confuse the left hand and the right hand of God, the hand of reason, law and philosophy, and the hand of faith, grace and theology!
Luther in his various disputations would occasionally quip that what was finally important in disputing was an agreement not merely in speech, but in the things (in res). An agreement as to what is held or asserted has been crucially important in the development of doctrine generally and within the Lutheran Confessions specifically. The question is this: How does this Lutheran commitment to the truth of propositions from the tradition and the Confessions get appropriated in our time? My considered opinion is that there is a great deal of confusion here, and my fear is that this confusion could be disastrous for the future of Lutheran theology.
When one plays baseball, one plays by baseball rules. There are three outs per side, both teams batting once constitutes an inning, and there are nine innings in a game. (I am thinking about the major and minor leagues with respect to this last point.) Proper theological language has rules as well. One must know how to use the word 'Father' and the word 'Son'. Specifically, one must be able to say 'The Son is God', 'The Father is God', without saying 'The Father is the Son'. Rules permitting the right expressions in the right linguistic circumstances and prohibiting the wrong ones in the wrong circumstances are notoriously difficult to formulate, but there is little doubt that there exist some set of rules that undergird the modus loquendi theologicus.
So far so good. One could in principle formulate a theological game as well as a game of black hole theory. Within contemporary cosmological theory, certain terms occur in particular statements and not within others. Prima facie there does not seem to be much different between the formal structure of a Trinitarian language and that language of any heavily theoretical discipline. There is a proper and improper way of using terms and phrases. The question now confronts us: Are the semantics of the two games the same?
On this there is much difference of opinion, of course. Many would say that there is extra-linguistic set of referents to which the language of black holes is anchored that is not available for the theoretical language of the Trinity. But why would this be so? Why would one think there is some res that black hole theory has the theology does not have? One would not think this - - unless one had previous opinions about what is possible ontologically for the Trinity over and against black holes.
Since the time of the Enlightenment, there has been an increasing sense in the former Christian West that the language of theology does not make truth claims. While most within popular culture - - I am not talking here about philosophers of science - - would claim that there are clear truth conditions for black hole theory, they would not, if they reflected some, claim easily that there are similar truth conditions in theology. The reason, of course, is that for tens of millions of people theological language simply can't be making truth claims because such language is an expression of individual and cultural value. There simply is no realm of theological facts such that the rules of theological language can govern a linguistic usage that can bring the language into contact with a domain of extra-linguistic referents. The fact/value distinction is wholly enshrined within contemporary culture, and this descendent from the Enlightenment must be dealt with before theological language is afforded the same opportunity to refer as the language of black holes.
My claim has been and continues to be that the interpretive center has been lost within much of Lutheran theology in the first part of the twenty-first century. The problem has been that a general cultural/intellectual commitment to the Enlightenment paradigm, especially Kant, has led millions to presuppose different semantic possibilities for that language than that which generally characterized the tradition. I am not saying that much of this is explicit. (Increasingly few people even know the name 'Kant'.) But middle school children learn that science is about facts and religion is about values. They don't know the torturous intellectual history that brought civilization to this "insight." They are taught this fact/value distinction as if it fell from the heavens. It is part of the Enlightenment paradigm, a paradigm that functions as the default ontological posit of our time. What I am saying is this: To continue to divorce theology and metaphysics and to allow the fact/value distinction to stand inviolate, is to allow theological language not to be about truth, and it is thus to allow theological language to assume a different semantics than it previously had.
The Institute of Lutheran Theology is grounded in Scripture and Confessions. It holds assiduously to classical confessional Lutheran theology. Professors at ILT are passionate about their commitment to Scriptural truth and authority as it is known and understood through the hermeneutical lens of the Confessions. While students are exposed to the great Biblical exegetes and the great theologians of the tradition, they learn the most important thing, I believe, that a school of theology can impart: ILT believes that it is true that God was in Jesus Christ reconciling the world unto Himself, and that because of this truth we have good grounds to preach and teach in His Name.
Saturday, May 26, 2012
A Lutheran School of Theology for our Times
Many of you know that I have been intimately involved with the effort to birth a new Lutheran School of Theology. It was, in fact, in 2006 that I began in earnest to work with others in forming the Institute of Lutheran Theology (ILT). It is now six years later and ILT (www.ilt.org) has moved from the nascent, through the initial fledgling, and into the mature fledgling stage. We are a staff of thirteen individuals, some living in Brookings, SD, but others living in places as diverse as Annapolis, New York, and Irvine, CA. We are a permanent faculty of nine with more than a dozen adjuncts teaching for us regularly. We are governed by a Board of eight prominent individuals from all parts of North America. This fall we are are expecting between 40-50 students studying in our degree and pastoral certificate programs.
ILT has been making strides in building its academic programs. We now have Masters of Arts degrees in Biblical Studies, in Theology, and in Religion, as well as our Masters of Divinity program. We are very excited about our Masters of Sacred Theology degree which allows students an opportunity to get a theology degree beyond the Masters of Divinity. This fall in the STM program, I will be teaching the Methodology course and Dr. Paul Hinlicky will be offering a Seminar on Pannenberg's three volume systematic theology. While ILT is still in its infancy, it is growing quickly.
I believe the ILT is a Lutheran School of Theology for our times. Why? The answer is simply that it fits nicely the post-modern context in which it finds itself. Modernity was a time in which the general commitment to the ideals of reason and objectivity tended to push theology in the direction of finding underlying commonalities among traditions. Notably, in the nineteenth century, attempts were made to ground all religion upon underlying structures of human feeling, morality, will or thinking. While the anthropological starting point was rejected in the twentieth century generally, it proved clearly difficult to formulate within a modernist paradigm a theory of the "Wholly Other," an account of the otherness of God that nonetheless accepted the Kantian critique.
Within the Lutheran situation in North America, modernity did not until the last 70 years or so, globally undermine the putative objects of religious experience and reflection. The trajectory of North American Lutheranism was dominated by another more modest and regional modernist impulse: the desire to find commonality in belief and practice and thus to form one large Lutheran denomination. Lutheran ecumenism seemed to entail structural unity. If two denominational trajectories could agree upon the same theological and ecclesiological principles, then they should become one trajectory. Conversely, if two trajectories were not to become one trajectory, they must have determinate theological and ecclesiological differences. Why else would they not become one? And if they held determinately different theological and ecclesiological views, then there must exist theological institutions whose purpose it was, in part, to give legitimacy to the distinctiveness of the disparate trajectories. Cooperation among seminaries across denominational lines was a risky thing indeed because it tended to undercut the legitimization of the disparate denominations themselves. Moreover, for different denominational traditions to use the same seminary was to suggest that there was no reason for there to be different denominational traditions in the first place.
But new cultural winds have been blowing, winds that have tended to erode the grounds of universal reason and objectivity upon which modernity was based. The result has been that increasing numbers of people are comfortable with contextualized, regional rationalities (and pluralism), and perspectivalism. While in many ways destructive of the traditional intellectual enterprise of the West, in others ways this move to postmodernity has been a move towards intellectual liberation: No longer does a tradition have to seek its legitimacy by arguing against a universal rational yardstick that it has a closer approximation to truth than another tradition. This externalist perspective is traded in for an internalist viewpoint: One starts on the inside in a tradition and experiences and reflects upon the world from the inside. There is no Archimedian view from the top - - a "view from nowhere." There are only traditions with there traditional ways of interpreting the world. Our resultant ideology of "inclusiveness in diversity" is built upon a postmodern scaffolding. Institutions must be inclusive of various diverse traditions, realizing the full complexity of what a tradition is and how a tradition comes to see the world in a particular way.
ILT is not a seminary of any denomination, but is a School of Theology dedicated to serving various denominational traditions. Its unity is found in its service to diverging theological traditions. It is not owned by a denomination, but is an independent, Lutheran non-profit entity that safeguards its autonomy and works towards its accreditation. Grounded in both Scripture and the Lutheran Confessions, yet realizing there has been and always will be diverging paths of Lutheran interpretation on both Scripture and Confessions, ILT seeks to connect the best Lutheran professors to the most capable Lutheran students using the latest interactive video-conferencing technology.
But the unity-in-diversity of ILT does have its limits in its interpretation of Scripture and Confessions. We believe, in fact, that both sources presuppose the following:
ILT has been making strides in building its academic programs. We now have Masters of Arts degrees in Biblical Studies, in Theology, and in Religion, as well as our Masters of Divinity program. We are very excited about our Masters of Sacred Theology degree which allows students an opportunity to get a theology degree beyond the Masters of Divinity. This fall in the STM program, I will be teaching the Methodology course and Dr. Paul Hinlicky will be offering a Seminar on Pannenberg's three volume systematic theology. While ILT is still in its infancy, it is growing quickly.
I believe the ILT is a Lutheran School of Theology for our times. Why? The answer is simply that it fits nicely the post-modern context in which it finds itself. Modernity was a time in which the general commitment to the ideals of reason and objectivity tended to push theology in the direction of finding underlying commonalities among traditions. Notably, in the nineteenth century, attempts were made to ground all religion upon underlying structures of human feeling, morality, will or thinking. While the anthropological starting point was rejected in the twentieth century generally, it proved clearly difficult to formulate within a modernist paradigm a theory of the "Wholly Other," an account of the otherness of God that nonetheless accepted the Kantian critique.
Within the Lutheran situation in North America, modernity did not until the last 70 years or so, globally undermine the putative objects of religious experience and reflection. The trajectory of North American Lutheranism was dominated by another more modest and regional modernist impulse: the desire to find commonality in belief and practice and thus to form one large Lutheran denomination. Lutheran ecumenism seemed to entail structural unity. If two denominational trajectories could agree upon the same theological and ecclesiological principles, then they should become one trajectory. Conversely, if two trajectories were not to become one trajectory, they must have determinate theological and ecclesiological differences. Why else would they not become one? And if they held determinately different theological and ecclesiological views, then there must exist theological institutions whose purpose it was, in part, to give legitimacy to the distinctiveness of the disparate trajectories. Cooperation among seminaries across denominational lines was a risky thing indeed because it tended to undercut the legitimization of the disparate denominations themselves. Moreover, for different denominational traditions to use the same seminary was to suggest that there was no reason for there to be different denominational traditions in the first place.
But new cultural winds have been blowing, winds that have tended to erode the grounds of universal reason and objectivity upon which modernity was based. The result has been that increasing numbers of people are comfortable with contextualized, regional rationalities (and pluralism), and perspectivalism. While in many ways destructive of the traditional intellectual enterprise of the West, in others ways this move to postmodernity has been a move towards intellectual liberation: No longer does a tradition have to seek its legitimacy by arguing against a universal rational yardstick that it has a closer approximation to truth than another tradition. This externalist perspective is traded in for an internalist viewpoint: One starts on the inside in a tradition and experiences and reflects upon the world from the inside. There is no Archimedian view from the top - - a "view from nowhere." There are only traditions with there traditional ways of interpreting the world. Our resultant ideology of "inclusiveness in diversity" is built upon a postmodern scaffolding. Institutions must be inclusive of various diverse traditions, realizing the full complexity of what a tradition is and how a tradition comes to see the world in a particular way.
ILT is not a seminary of any denomination, but is a School of Theology dedicated to serving various denominational traditions. Its unity is found in its service to diverging theological traditions. It is not owned by a denomination, but is an independent, Lutheran non-profit entity that safeguards its autonomy and works towards its accreditation. Grounded in both Scripture and the Lutheran Confessions, yet realizing there has been and always will be diverging paths of Lutheran interpretation on both Scripture and Confessions, ILT seeks to connect the best Lutheran professors to the most capable Lutheran students using the latest interactive video-conferencing technology.
But the unity-in-diversity of ILT does have its limits in its interpretation of Scripture and Confessions. We believe, in fact, that both sources presuppose the following:
- There is a God who has its being apart from human awareness, perception, conception and language.
- Propositions about God and God's relation to the world can be true or false.
- God and the world can be (and are) causally related.
- God's work in Jesus Christ cannot be confined merely to the realm of value, but also concerns the realm of nature.
- Scripture has both an external and internal clarity.
Friday, May 25, 2012
Living Under the Epistemic Law
Clearly, it is plausible to claim that warrant is what separates true belief and knowledge. The received view in epistemology is that knowledge just is justified, true belief, and while the post-Gettier literature has tried to tweak this a bit so as to avoid unintended counterinstances, the central idea remains intact: Something more than true belief is needed for knowledge, and this something more is what warrants the epistemic agent holding that true belief at all. But what is this warrant?
Many hold that warrant connects generally to deontology as follows: x is warranted for Y if and only if Y concludes x when acting on the basis of properly performing all of his/her epistemic duties. The idea is that a proper concluding of x is somehow internal to Y-- that the relevant warrant-conferring properties are internal to Y, i.e., that Y's mental states are pertinent in concluding x. There are many ways to be an internalist, but normativity usually figures into to all of them in some way. If one, broadly speaking, manifests proper doxastic practice, then one will have a greater probability in ascertaining truth. Acting due to the proper rule or law of proper doxastic formation adds warrant to true belief and thus issues in knowledge. (I am skipping over many philosophical details here in order to get at the theological issue.)
Famously, William Clifford argued that it was always wrong everywhere to hold a belief without proper grounds or evidence. In so arguing, Clifford committed himself to the importance of the epistemic law in achieving knowledge. One's ship might make it across the ocean or it might not. To say that one knows that it will do so without having proper evidence - - without properly performing one's pertinent epistemic duties - - is the mark of epistemic waywardness. One only knows that it will so make it if one has done the relevant research, believes it will make it and it does so. Absent the relevant research, even if it happens to make it across, one cannot say that one knew it, though one did believe it deeply. The idea is that one is responsible for what one claims to know. One cannot know that which one has not examined deeply. Simply put, it can be clearly irresponsible to say one knows that the ship will make it even if it does, while one might responsibly hold claim to know that the ship will make it even if it does not. Such epistemic responsibility is tied to the proper performance of epistemic duty.
There is thus a parallel between the proper formation of belief and the proper performance of an action, a parallel eschewing of consequentialism. Just as the ethical deontologist holds that acting due to a moral principle in performing A clan be right even if the consequences of A are in fact deleterious, so does the epistemic deontologist claim that forming a belief due to properly performing one's epistemic duties is right even if the belief turns out to be false. Everything rests upon the intentionality of the act. Was the moral act done solely on the basis of the moral law? Was the epistemic act done solely on the basis of the epistemic principle? Deontology in epistemology makes knowing a matter of the law. One must properly perform one's epistemic duties if one is ever to achieve knowledge. Simply put, if one is to know x, one must do what one ought to do.
But human beings have not been successful in doing what they ought to do. While Bob should act on the basis of moral principle P, he does not so act. Why? Christians confess that there is a basic existential disruption that does not allow Bob to act as he ought. Sin is that which prohibits the total consonance of "is" and "ought."
But what is true of moral action is true also of epistemology. Why would anyone expect epistemic agent Bob always to act due to the proper epistemic principle? There same is/ought gap exists in epistemology as it does in moral action generally. "Oh, sinful epistemic agent that I am, those things I claim to know, I do not really know!" Descartes famously argued that epistemic turpitude rests upon human beings having freedom to assert P or not assert P, and that unfortunately they do assert one (or the other) without adequate grounds. (God does not have this failing having always adequate grounds.) Epistemic waywardness is built into the fabric of human existence.
Lutherans claim that the nature of the Law is always to accuse. While I try to live my life in accordance with the proper moral principles, I cannot do so. Thus, I am guilty. Similarly and in an epistemic key, while I try to live my life in accordance with proper epistemic duties, I cannot do so. Thus, I am guilty.
To be guilty is finally not to be who one deeply is. As sons and daughters of God created in imago dei, we ought always to do that which would properly issue from one created in imago dei. But we don't so act and thus we aren't so constituted.
Lutheran theology proclaims grace to all who stand guilty before the Law. While we are not now who we ought to be, in God's sight - - i.e., the highest sight - - we become again who we should be. The accusing Law is quelled through the effects of God's love of us. Through Christ we are again who we really are even though, and despite the fact, we are not who we should be. The way that grace makes us who we truly are, while we yet remain who we are not truly, is a subject of great controversy in the theological tradition. The distinction between intrinsic and extrinsic grace is important in examining these ways. Is the grace which heals the disrupture something that human beings in some sense have (and on the logical basis of which a divine judgment is proffered), or is it some change of the divine judgment (on the logical basis of which human change is possible? (We shall not go into all of the views here, but readers of the blog probably are familiar with most.)
The question, however, of this post is this: If there is a parallel between the moral and epistemic waywardness of human beings in that both the morality and epistemology ultimately depend upon the law, and if this law always accuses us because we are not the moral (and epistemic agents) we ought to be, and if our healing from the guilt of moral sin is due to grace (however, finally considered), then would it not be important for Christians (of a deontological internalist persuasion) to reflect upon what the contour of what epistemic grace might be? If we cannot live up to our paridisical epistemic lights, and if living in accordance with these lights is what it is to have true knowledge of truth, then what divine grace might we expect in knowing truth?
On this way of viewing things, the Tree of the Knowledge of Good and Evil really symbolizes a fall into the deontological, both moral and epistemic. Thinking through what knowledge could be before such a Fall is the theme of a later post. It seems clear, however, that it cannot be a matter of deontology.
Many hold that warrant connects generally to deontology as follows: x is warranted for Y if and only if Y concludes x when acting on the basis of properly performing all of his/her epistemic duties. The idea is that a proper concluding of x is somehow internal to Y-- that the relevant warrant-conferring properties are internal to Y, i.e., that Y's mental states are pertinent in concluding x. There are many ways to be an internalist, but normativity usually figures into to all of them in some way. If one, broadly speaking, manifests proper doxastic practice, then one will have a greater probability in ascertaining truth. Acting due to the proper rule or law of proper doxastic formation adds warrant to true belief and thus issues in knowledge. (I am skipping over many philosophical details here in order to get at the theological issue.)
Famously, William Clifford argued that it was always wrong everywhere to hold a belief without proper grounds or evidence. In so arguing, Clifford committed himself to the importance of the epistemic law in achieving knowledge. One's ship might make it across the ocean or it might not. To say that one knows that it will do so without having proper evidence - - without properly performing one's pertinent epistemic duties - - is the mark of epistemic waywardness. One only knows that it will so make it if one has done the relevant research, believes it will make it and it does so. Absent the relevant research, even if it happens to make it across, one cannot say that one knew it, though one did believe it deeply. The idea is that one is responsible for what one claims to know. One cannot know that which one has not examined deeply. Simply put, it can be clearly irresponsible to say one knows that the ship will make it even if it does, while one might responsibly hold claim to know that the ship will make it even if it does not. Such epistemic responsibility is tied to the proper performance of epistemic duty.
There is thus a parallel between the proper formation of belief and the proper performance of an action, a parallel eschewing of consequentialism. Just as the ethical deontologist holds that acting due to a moral principle in performing A clan be right even if the consequences of A are in fact deleterious, so does the epistemic deontologist claim that forming a belief due to properly performing one's epistemic duties is right even if the belief turns out to be false. Everything rests upon the intentionality of the act. Was the moral act done solely on the basis of the moral law? Was the epistemic act done solely on the basis of the epistemic principle? Deontology in epistemology makes knowing a matter of the law. One must properly perform one's epistemic duties if one is ever to achieve knowledge. Simply put, if one is to know x, one must do what one ought to do.
But human beings have not been successful in doing what they ought to do. While Bob should act on the basis of moral principle P, he does not so act. Why? Christians confess that there is a basic existential disruption that does not allow Bob to act as he ought. Sin is that which prohibits the total consonance of "is" and "ought."
But what is true of moral action is true also of epistemology. Why would anyone expect epistemic agent Bob always to act due to the proper epistemic principle? There same is/ought gap exists in epistemology as it does in moral action generally. "Oh, sinful epistemic agent that I am, those things I claim to know, I do not really know!" Descartes famously argued that epistemic turpitude rests upon human beings having freedom to assert P or not assert P, and that unfortunately they do assert one (or the other) without adequate grounds. (God does not have this failing having always adequate grounds.) Epistemic waywardness is built into the fabric of human existence.
Lutherans claim that the nature of the Law is always to accuse. While I try to live my life in accordance with the proper moral principles, I cannot do so. Thus, I am guilty. Similarly and in an epistemic key, while I try to live my life in accordance with proper epistemic duties, I cannot do so. Thus, I am guilty.
To be guilty is finally not to be who one deeply is. As sons and daughters of God created in imago dei, we ought always to do that which would properly issue from one created in imago dei. But we don't so act and thus we aren't so constituted.
Lutheran theology proclaims grace to all who stand guilty before the Law. While we are not now who we ought to be, in God's sight - - i.e., the highest sight - - we become again who we should be. The accusing Law is quelled through the effects of God's love of us. Through Christ we are again who we really are even though, and despite the fact, we are not who we should be. The way that grace makes us who we truly are, while we yet remain who we are not truly, is a subject of great controversy in the theological tradition. The distinction between intrinsic and extrinsic grace is important in examining these ways. Is the grace which heals the disrupture something that human beings in some sense have (and on the logical basis of which a divine judgment is proffered), or is it some change of the divine judgment (on the logical basis of which human change is possible? (We shall not go into all of the views here, but readers of the blog probably are familiar with most.)
The question, however, of this post is this: If there is a parallel between the moral and epistemic waywardness of human beings in that both the morality and epistemology ultimately depend upon the law, and if this law always accuses us because we are not the moral (and epistemic agents) we ought to be, and if our healing from the guilt of moral sin is due to grace (however, finally considered), then would it not be important for Christians (of a deontological internalist persuasion) to reflect upon what the contour of what epistemic grace might be? If we cannot live up to our paridisical epistemic lights, and if living in accordance with these lights is what it is to have true knowledge of truth, then what divine grace might we expect in knowing truth?
On this way of viewing things, the Tree of the Knowledge of Good and Evil really symbolizes a fall into the deontological, both moral and epistemic. Thinking through what knowledge could be before such a Fall is the theme of a later post. It seems clear, however, that it cannot be a matter of deontology.
Labels:
epistemology,
grace,
Law,
Lutheran Theology
Friday, May 04, 2012
Transcendentality
I must admit that I have always rather liked the transcendental option. When the skies seem especially dark, it is tempting to think of divine presence on the transcendental horizon of our own experience. This way of proceeding supposedly avoids the problems of subjectivism and pyschologism without committing one to finding God as an object among objects in the world and history, or looking for Him in some supernatural transcendent dimension lying out beyond the world and history.
I admit that I have not thought much about the transcendental starting point in recent years. Instead I have been pondering how it is that in order to avoid an eliminativism of the theological, one must ascribe to it a robust semantics, one that is realist in its orientation.
I want to relfect here a bit upon transcendentality and the semantic questions that arise when trying to articulate the position. While the transcendental starting point is prima facie promising in trying to locate a place for God, the position requires a type of realist semantics that is difficult to formulate. I will try to lay this out nascently below.
Transcendental Thomism was part of a general effort within mid-twentieth century Roman Catholicism to read Aquinas in ways that were not Neo-Scholastic in orientation. The idea was to retrieve the Augustinian element in Thomas' thinking which would allow God to be found grounding the activity of human intentionality itself.
Reflect for a moment on the grasping of any being. The necessary condition for grasping determinate being is, for Karl Rahner - - the most famous of the Transcendental Thomists - - that one have a pre-understanding, or a fore-grasping of Being in itself. In every act of knowing any object, there is a transcendental condition consisting in the a horizon of pure being. This horizon is the term of the Vorgriff, the end point of any fore-grasping. The idea is very simple and maybe an analogy helps. In order for a person to know that she is incarcerated in a particular cell, she must grasp beyond the cell to know what area she could be occupying if she were not limited by the cell wall to be in the particular cell she is in. Without a fore-grasping of the "beyond," the incarcerated one would not know themselves as incarcerated at all. Whereas Heidegger said that projecting into no-thing was the necessary condition for the thing to be thing - - and hence "nothingness is the face of being" - - Karl Rahner claimed that the totality of Being is the face of being.
The transcendental starting point fits nicely within the Augustinian key, within the general orientation of "the ontological thirst," that is, the thematization of the assertion that "my heart is not at rest until it finds its rest in Thee, O Lord." Human beings are a dynamism towards Being. This dynamism towards Being is the transcendental condition for the possibility of grasping the realm of determinate beings.
Very important in this approach is the overcoming of Neo-Scholastic dualisms between nature and supernature, the finite and infinite, and nature and grace. The transcendental horizon making possible human knowledge is not merely a thing of nature, nor merely a thing of grace, but it is a horizon of a continuum of nature and grace, a continuum where natural human striving gives way to the grace of God as pure Being, as that which is the authentic end of human striving. For Rahner and followers nature is already graced; God is always already related to nature. Grace thus is ingredient in the transcendental constitution of natural human striving; there is no authentic nature without grace.
Now the question I wish to entertain pertains to the semantics of the language I have just used to articulate the position in the previous three paragraphs. What are the conditions for the possibility of meaning and truth of that language used to articulate the structure of the transcendental horizon of human natural being?
This is a very difficult question, of course; one that seems far more difficult than articulating the conditions for the possibility of the meaningfulness of language referring to the world of nature and history, or a putative transcendent realm existing beyond nature and history.
I have argued that we must adopt semantic realism in theology for three reasons: 1) If our time is to take the truth claims of theology seriously again, theology must make serious truth claims; 2) If theology is a discipline that is so important that one's very being and the meaning of one's being is at issue in it, then we should work with a view of theological language that makes the most robust theological assertions; 3) It turns out to be very difficult to give theological language a self-consistent semantic interpretation that is finally not realist - - at least if one wants to retain theological language. Because semantic realism seems best for referring to God in the world and beyond it, it is tempting to think that semantic realism is the best construal of language about the transcendental horizon as well. However, for reasons soon apparent it proves to be very difficult indeed to provide such a semantics. Why?
Imagine language L having a standard intension and extension such that the intension of a name is its sense and its extension is its reference, the intension of a monadic predicate is a property and its extension a set of objects satisfying that property, that the intension of a polyadic predicate is a relation and its extension the set of ordered n-tuples satisfying this relation, and the intension of a sentence is the proposition expressed and the extension its truth-value. Now assume the L is going to articulate the transcendental horizon T.
The first question to ask is what are the names that refer to objects and entities, and what are the predicates that refer to classes of objects and entities? Whereas a particular being is an object, it is not clear that the horizon of being is itself an entity or object. But what is it? Is it precisely that which is forgotten in any predicate of the predicate to the name? This sounds sufficiently profound, but what could be actually said by saying that there is something that is not a being or thing but still nevertheless is somehow, and that this which is but is not any particular being is that which is forgotten in the very semantics of L?
Now one might say that the particular dynamism toward Being itself is a series of events that could be specified in principle by names, and that the property of "driving beyond" refers to the class of those events comprising the dynamism. On this construal, the dynamism and its salient properties could be in principle referred to by L, But notice what can't be referred to? It is precisely the term of the Vorgriff, the end or being towards which the dynamism flows.
But I hear the objection. Have you not in this proto-analysis presupposed a dualism between self and other, with the otherness of Being Itself now somehow existing outside the dynamnism as that to which the dynamism flows? Don't you realize that it is precisely, as you earlier said, a continuum that exists between the dynamism and its terms, and thus between nature and grace? But unfortunately pointing this out is no ultimate help at all to the semantic task. Why?
The reason why is analogous to the problem Wittgenstein had in the Tractatus. After he pointed out that language can have sense only when it refers to objects in the world, he raised the question of the meaningfulness of the assertions which themselves refer to the relation between language and world. Obviously, they must be senseless. Wittgenstein thus concludes the Tractatus with the suggestion that the propositions of the Tractatus are elucidations, that they are like the rungs on the ladder, the entire ladder of which must be thrown away when the relationship between world and language is rightly grasped.
Analogically here, the transcendental horizon of the graced natural dynamism towards being (T) grounds the very possibility of the language used to talk about that transcendental horizon. In the human dynamism towards Being in its totality, the transcendental horizon T is known in the surpassing towards being. However, since Being in its totality cannot be an other to the subject of the transcendental dynamism, Being in its totality becomes the face of Being in its totality, that is, the articulating of the transcendental structure presupposes the transcendental structure. Language about being which grasps determinate being having the transcendental horizon as a condition cannot itself grasp indeterminate being, that is, it cannot grasp the transcendental structure having as its ultimate term the totality of being.
Nothing what I have said here should be deeply surprising. Why would one expect language to be able to refer to something as inchoate an unthematic as the transcendental horizon of being? My embryonic point here is simply this: If transcendentality is the ultimate location of God, then the infinite regress of transcendentality in knowing transcendentality is a problem for any language that attempts to state this. Clearly, language L is not adequate to the task of referring to the transcendental horizon. If this is so - - and I do know that much more argument is needed - - then hopes appear dim for a semantic realism with regard to transcendentality, and accordingly, for the robust truth of the existence and contour of transcendentality itself.
I admit that I have not thought much about the transcendental starting point in recent years. Instead I have been pondering how it is that in order to avoid an eliminativism of the theological, one must ascribe to it a robust semantics, one that is realist in its orientation.
I want to relfect here a bit upon transcendentality and the semantic questions that arise when trying to articulate the position. While the transcendental starting point is prima facie promising in trying to locate a place for God, the position requires a type of realist semantics that is difficult to formulate. I will try to lay this out nascently below.
Transcendental Thomism was part of a general effort within mid-twentieth century Roman Catholicism to read Aquinas in ways that were not Neo-Scholastic in orientation. The idea was to retrieve the Augustinian element in Thomas' thinking which would allow God to be found grounding the activity of human intentionality itself.
Reflect for a moment on the grasping of any being. The necessary condition for grasping determinate being is, for Karl Rahner - - the most famous of the Transcendental Thomists - - that one have a pre-understanding, or a fore-grasping of Being in itself. In every act of knowing any object, there is a transcendental condition consisting in the a horizon of pure being. This horizon is the term of the Vorgriff, the end point of any fore-grasping. The idea is very simple and maybe an analogy helps. In order for a person to know that she is incarcerated in a particular cell, she must grasp beyond the cell to know what area she could be occupying if she were not limited by the cell wall to be in the particular cell she is in. Without a fore-grasping of the "beyond," the incarcerated one would not know themselves as incarcerated at all. Whereas Heidegger said that projecting into no-thing was the necessary condition for the thing to be thing - - and hence "nothingness is the face of being" - - Karl Rahner claimed that the totality of Being is the face of being.
The transcendental starting point fits nicely within the Augustinian key, within the general orientation of "the ontological thirst," that is, the thematization of the assertion that "my heart is not at rest until it finds its rest in Thee, O Lord." Human beings are a dynamism towards Being. This dynamism towards Being is the transcendental condition for the possibility of grasping the realm of determinate beings.
Very important in this approach is the overcoming of Neo-Scholastic dualisms between nature and supernature, the finite and infinite, and nature and grace. The transcendental horizon making possible human knowledge is not merely a thing of nature, nor merely a thing of grace, but it is a horizon of a continuum of nature and grace, a continuum where natural human striving gives way to the grace of God as pure Being, as that which is the authentic end of human striving. For Rahner and followers nature is already graced; God is always already related to nature. Grace thus is ingredient in the transcendental constitution of natural human striving; there is no authentic nature without grace.
Now the question I wish to entertain pertains to the semantics of the language I have just used to articulate the position in the previous three paragraphs. What are the conditions for the possibility of meaning and truth of that language used to articulate the structure of the transcendental horizon of human natural being?
This is a very difficult question, of course; one that seems far more difficult than articulating the conditions for the possibility of the meaningfulness of language referring to the world of nature and history, or a putative transcendent realm existing beyond nature and history.
I have argued that we must adopt semantic realism in theology for three reasons: 1) If our time is to take the truth claims of theology seriously again, theology must make serious truth claims; 2) If theology is a discipline that is so important that one's very being and the meaning of one's being is at issue in it, then we should work with a view of theological language that makes the most robust theological assertions; 3) It turns out to be very difficult to give theological language a self-consistent semantic interpretation that is finally not realist - - at least if one wants to retain theological language. Because semantic realism seems best for referring to God in the world and beyond it, it is tempting to think that semantic realism is the best construal of language about the transcendental horizon as well. However, for reasons soon apparent it proves to be very difficult indeed to provide such a semantics. Why?
Imagine language L having a standard intension and extension such that the intension of a name is its sense and its extension is its reference, the intension of a monadic predicate is a property and its extension a set of objects satisfying that property, that the intension of a polyadic predicate is a relation and its extension the set of ordered n-tuples satisfying this relation, and the intension of a sentence is the proposition expressed and the extension its truth-value. Now assume the L is going to articulate the transcendental horizon T.
The first question to ask is what are the names that refer to objects and entities, and what are the predicates that refer to classes of objects and entities? Whereas a particular being is an object, it is not clear that the horizon of being is itself an entity or object. But what is it? Is it precisely that which is forgotten in any predicate of the predicate to the name? This sounds sufficiently profound, but what could be actually said by saying that there is something that is not a being or thing but still nevertheless is somehow, and that this which is but is not any particular being is that which is forgotten in the very semantics of L?
Now one might say that the particular dynamism toward Being itself is a series of events that could be specified in principle by names, and that the property of "driving beyond" refers to the class of those events comprising the dynamism. On this construal, the dynamism and its salient properties could be in principle referred to by L, But notice what can't be referred to? It is precisely the term of the Vorgriff, the end or being towards which the dynamism flows.
But I hear the objection. Have you not in this proto-analysis presupposed a dualism between self and other, with the otherness of Being Itself now somehow existing outside the dynamnism as that to which the dynamism flows? Don't you realize that it is precisely, as you earlier said, a continuum that exists between the dynamism and its terms, and thus between nature and grace? But unfortunately pointing this out is no ultimate help at all to the semantic task. Why?
The reason why is analogous to the problem Wittgenstein had in the Tractatus. After he pointed out that language can have sense only when it refers to objects in the world, he raised the question of the meaningfulness of the assertions which themselves refer to the relation between language and world. Obviously, they must be senseless. Wittgenstein thus concludes the Tractatus with the suggestion that the propositions of the Tractatus are elucidations, that they are like the rungs on the ladder, the entire ladder of which must be thrown away when the relationship between world and language is rightly grasped.
Analogically here, the transcendental horizon of the graced natural dynamism towards being (T) grounds the very possibility of the language used to talk about that transcendental horizon. In the human dynamism towards Being in its totality, the transcendental horizon T is known in the surpassing towards being. However, since Being in its totality cannot be an other to the subject of the transcendental dynamism, Being in its totality becomes the face of Being in its totality, that is, the articulating of the transcendental structure presupposes the transcendental structure. Language about being which grasps determinate being having the transcendental horizon as a condition cannot itself grasp indeterminate being, that is, it cannot grasp the transcendental structure having as its ultimate term the totality of being.
Nothing what I have said here should be deeply surprising. Why would one expect language to be able to refer to something as inchoate an unthematic as the transcendental horizon of being? My embryonic point here is simply this: If transcendentality is the ultimate location of God, then the infinite regress of transcendentality in knowing transcendentality is a problem for any language that attempts to state this. Clearly, language L is not adequate to the task of referring to the transcendental horizon. If this is so - - and I do know that much more argument is needed - - then hopes appear dim for a semantic realism with regard to transcendentality, and accordingly, for the robust truth of the existence and contour of transcendentality itself.
Monday, January 09, 2012
Semantics and Correlative Theology
There was once a time when I did not worry too much about how talk of God and talk of the universe as such connected. In those days I solidly subscribed to a correlative theology which linked the semantics of theological language to the semantics of human existential/phenomenological/ontological language. Theological truth and meaning had to do with human truth and meaning. The language of each could be mapped to an appropriate background language such that the discourse of theology was commensurate with that of theology. While the logical geography of fundamental ontology differed from that of theology, they could be compared. Existential questions could be given theological answers, and theological answers would invite existential questions.
Over the years I have come to regard this effort as being more or less misguided. It is not that existential questions cannot be correlated with religious answers, it is simply that when this is done, the religious answer correlated has a different meaning than it would have had were it not so correlated. How is this so?
Religious and theological answers pertain to soteriology, and what is salvific with respect to our immediate situation in the universe is not likely the same thing as what is salvific when our immediate situation is worked up existentially-phenomenologically-orntologically. (I realize that this statement needs a considerable amount of unpacking.) A corollary to what I am saying is simply that a problem with the method of correlation is that it cannot save the one that correlates. This method is to the philosophy of science what lived salvific immediacy is to the practice of science.
It is finally a question of semantics. For C (the one correlating), existential question E has a definite meaning that can in some way be addressed by theological answer T. E and T have more or less definite semantic conditions for C. Think, however, about one who has not adopted the reflexive standpoint of C. Let us call such a non-reflexive one U (standing for unable of willing to occupy the standpoint of C). For U, T has different meaning and truth conditions than for C because the truth conditions for T are ontological - - one might better say 'ontic' here because I am talking about being not the be-ing of beings - - in a way that they are not for C.
How is this so? Clearly, the truth conditions for T with respect to U are tied to what is the case in a way that T is not for C. Accordingly for C, T is true just in case T obtains. But this need not be so for C. Here T is true just in case it is appropriately linked to E. For U, T is true just in case a relationship R holds appropriately of some state of affairs S. For C, T is true just in case a relationship R' hold appropriately of some religious or theological description D that is pertinent to E. For U, T is true because of some reality that is what it is apart from human awareness, perception, conception and language. This is an extensionalist interpretation of T. For C, since T is true just because there is a reality which is what it is because of human awareness, perception, conception or language, the description of this reality becomes the most important matter. Now we have moved to an intensionalist context. (This needs more unpacking as well.)
If I have not made myself sufficiently clear in the proceeding paragraph, let me try again. The theologian who believes there is some extra-linguistic, extra-subjective ontological situation that obtains from which one must be saved, will regard the meaning of that which saves to be of a different type than the theologian who does not believe this. The move to the reflexive level is indeed a move out of the primary soteriological context. The one making the move likely has reinterpreted the meaning of the soteriological context in ways that make it true that a real ontic answer no longer is necessary or warranted in addressing that context.
The question of which we are dealing concerns the identity conditions of theological and religious statements. What makes one theological proposition semantically identical to another? Identical syntax does not an identical semantics entail, for theological propositions have different meanings within different contexts. Semantics does not supervene upon syntax unless the syntax is defined to include the very form of life of the one using the syntax. (One might then talk about a global supervenience of semantics upon syntax.) The identity of theological propositions is clearly not externally related to the philosophical (ontological) context in which they find themselves and to which they are related. The point is that the context of reflexive correlation is a very different context than immediate lived existence.
A related question of identity within theological semantics arises for the theologian who believes that the content of preaching Christ and Him crucified is somehow identical across various philosophical and metaphysical worldviews. Wilhelm Hermann argued famously that metaphysics is irrelevant to theology. That is to say, presumably, that the semantic identity of a certain set of theological statements is invariant across different ontological worldviews, across worldviews as different as nineteenth century materialism and teleological Aristotelianism. The semantics of theological propositions are indifferent to the greater philosophical context, that is, to alternate sets of philosophical presuppositions.
But this cannot possibly be the case. What a theological proposition means is fundamentally connected to the context in which it finds itself, that is, to the wider philosophical context. It is very easy to see this is true, for the truth conditions of a theological proposition does in fact change across different ontological horizons. Why?
Imagine I hold that the proclamation that I am forgiven from my sins in spite of my sin is a performative utterance issuing in the perlocution of existential empowerment in the face of fundamental anxieties. Clearly, the semantics of the declarative utterance is related to the context of a linguistic/existential structure of human existence. The meaning of the declarative statement is not related to some kind of theological states of affairs, but rather to the human existential/linguistic structure. In this way, one might say that the Word is what it does.
However, the critical question is and has always been, is the Word only what it does. Is the perlocution itself the result of a belief about the world, or can the perlocution happen without such a belief? It has always seemed clear to me that the possibility of the perlocution occurring is tied to human belief in a very proximate way. Without the belief being the belief that it is, it is not the case that the perlocution is the perlocution that it is. Responding to the gospel declaration is not like hearing the words "excuse me." While the conventions of the social situation are present in the former, they do not determine the use and response to the gospel address in a similar way.
But the deeper question has to do with truth conditions themselves. If one says "God was in Christ reconciling the world to Himself," is it not quite different to say that the truth conditions are that God is in Jesus Christ, or alternately that they are somehow in the existential empowerment of the listener? Consider how different these two truth conditions are:
1) 'God is in Jesus Christ reconciling the world unto Himself' is true if and only if God is in Jesus Christ reconciling the world unto Himself.
2) 'God is in Jesus Christ reconciling the world unto Himself' is true if and only if the utterance of 'God is in Jesus Christ reconciling the world unto Himself' effects a particular hearer H (appropriately structured so as to be effected by the utterance), in such a way as to have existential empowerment of an appropriate kind,
While one could spend a great deal of time and effort trying to clarify (2), it should be apparent what the salient difference between (1) and (2) is. The meaning of the latter has to be defined relationally with respect to the human linguistic/existential structure; the meaning of the former can be defined by its relationship to a world that exists apart from human awareness, perception, conception and language.
Over the years I have come to regard this effort as being more or less misguided. It is not that existential questions cannot be correlated with religious answers, it is simply that when this is done, the religious answer correlated has a different meaning than it would have had were it not so correlated. How is this so?
Religious and theological answers pertain to soteriology, and what is salvific with respect to our immediate situation in the universe is not likely the same thing as what is salvific when our immediate situation is worked up existentially-phenomenologically-orntologically. (I realize that this statement needs a considerable amount of unpacking.) A corollary to what I am saying is simply that a problem with the method of correlation is that it cannot save the one that correlates. This method is to the philosophy of science what lived salvific immediacy is to the practice of science.
It is finally a question of semantics. For C (the one correlating), existential question E has a definite meaning that can in some way be addressed by theological answer T. E and T have more or less definite semantic conditions for C. Think, however, about one who has not adopted the reflexive standpoint of C. Let us call such a non-reflexive one U (standing for unable of willing to occupy the standpoint of C). For U, T has different meaning and truth conditions than for C because the truth conditions for T are ontological - - one might better say 'ontic' here because I am talking about being not the be-ing of beings - - in a way that they are not for C.
How is this so? Clearly, the truth conditions for T with respect to U are tied to what is the case in a way that T is not for C. Accordingly for C, T is true just in case T obtains. But this need not be so for C. Here T is true just in case it is appropriately linked to E. For U, T is true just in case a relationship R holds appropriately of some state of affairs S. For C, T is true just in case a relationship R' hold appropriately of some religious or theological description D that is pertinent to E. For U, T is true because of some reality that is what it is apart from human awareness, perception, conception and language. This is an extensionalist interpretation of T. For C, since T is true just because there is a reality which is what it is because of human awareness, perception, conception or language, the description of this reality becomes the most important matter. Now we have moved to an intensionalist context. (This needs more unpacking as well.)
If I have not made myself sufficiently clear in the proceeding paragraph, let me try again. The theologian who believes there is some extra-linguistic, extra-subjective ontological situation that obtains from which one must be saved, will regard the meaning of that which saves to be of a different type than the theologian who does not believe this. The move to the reflexive level is indeed a move out of the primary soteriological context. The one making the move likely has reinterpreted the meaning of the soteriological context in ways that make it true that a real ontic answer no longer is necessary or warranted in addressing that context.
The question of which we are dealing concerns the identity conditions of theological and religious statements. What makes one theological proposition semantically identical to another? Identical syntax does not an identical semantics entail, for theological propositions have different meanings within different contexts. Semantics does not supervene upon syntax unless the syntax is defined to include the very form of life of the one using the syntax. (One might then talk about a global supervenience of semantics upon syntax.) The identity of theological propositions is clearly not externally related to the philosophical (ontological) context in which they find themselves and to which they are related. The point is that the context of reflexive correlation is a very different context than immediate lived existence.
A related question of identity within theological semantics arises for the theologian who believes that the content of preaching Christ and Him crucified is somehow identical across various philosophical and metaphysical worldviews. Wilhelm Hermann argued famously that metaphysics is irrelevant to theology. That is to say, presumably, that the semantic identity of a certain set of theological statements is invariant across different ontological worldviews, across worldviews as different as nineteenth century materialism and teleological Aristotelianism. The semantics of theological propositions are indifferent to the greater philosophical context, that is, to alternate sets of philosophical presuppositions.
But this cannot possibly be the case. What a theological proposition means is fundamentally connected to the context in which it finds itself, that is, to the wider philosophical context. It is very easy to see this is true, for the truth conditions of a theological proposition does in fact change across different ontological horizons. Why?
Imagine I hold that the proclamation that I am forgiven from my sins in spite of my sin is a performative utterance issuing in the perlocution of existential empowerment in the face of fundamental anxieties. Clearly, the semantics of the declarative utterance is related to the context of a linguistic/existential structure of human existence. The meaning of the declarative statement is not related to some kind of theological states of affairs, but rather to the human existential/linguistic structure. In this way, one might say that the Word is what it does.
However, the critical question is and has always been, is the Word only what it does. Is the perlocution itself the result of a belief about the world, or can the perlocution happen without such a belief? It has always seemed clear to me that the possibility of the perlocution occurring is tied to human belief in a very proximate way. Without the belief being the belief that it is, it is not the case that the perlocution is the perlocution that it is. Responding to the gospel declaration is not like hearing the words "excuse me." While the conventions of the social situation are present in the former, they do not determine the use and response to the gospel address in a similar way.
But the deeper question has to do with truth conditions themselves. If one says "God was in Christ reconciling the world to Himself," is it not quite different to say that the truth conditions are that God is in Jesus Christ, or alternately that they are somehow in the existential empowerment of the listener? Consider how different these two truth conditions are:
1) 'God is in Jesus Christ reconciling the world unto Himself' is true if and only if God is in Jesus Christ reconciling the world unto Himself.
2) 'God is in Jesus Christ reconciling the world unto Himself' is true if and only if the utterance of 'God is in Jesus Christ reconciling the world unto Himself' effects a particular hearer H (appropriately structured so as to be effected by the utterance), in such a way as to have existential empowerment of an appropriate kind,
While one could spend a great deal of time and effort trying to clarify (2), it should be apparent what the salient difference between (1) and (2) is. The meaning of the latter has to be defined relationally with respect to the human linguistic/existential structure; the meaning of the former can be defined by its relationship to a world that exists apart from human awareness, perception, conception and language.
Sunday, December 04, 2011
The Big Problem for Lutheran Confessionalism
Thinkers like to think about things towards which progress can be made. Philosophers of a materialist or physicalist persuasion find it relatively easy to understand how properties at higher levels might covary as a function of properties at lower levels.
For instance, biological properties distribute as a function of chemical properties, which distribute as a function of molecular properties, which themselves distribute as a function of atomic properties or subatomic properties. While there are some problems relating levels, the big problem concerns how it is that psychological properties covary with respect to neurophysiological properties.
While we may have no difficulties in general in countenancing a view of things where neurophysiological actualizations are finally metaphysically dependent upon mircrophysical causation, the notion that thoughts and decisions might ultimately metaphysically depend upon mircophysical processes is disquieting. While moderate reductions seem unproblematic throughout physical reality, the countenancing of reductions between the mental and physical involves some rather paradoxical claims, e.g., the notion that my writing these words in this blog right now themselves metaphysically depend somehow upon microphysical actualizations of various kinds.
While some philosophers here warmly embrace the "downward causality" of the mental into the physical on a mereological basis, the fundamental problem remains: If mental event m1 causes neurophysiological actualizations p2, then it seems that m1 must either itself have a physical realization or not. If it has no physical realization, then the advocate of downward causation must finally advocate a substance dualism - - something they want to avoid - - or she or he must admit that the physical realizer of m1 - - let us call this p1 -- itself causes p2, and there is no real downward causation. So the big problem is simply this: How is genuine freedom possible for an agent when the agent and his/her acts are metaphysically dependent upon microphysics? The problem is so big and intractable, that philosophers generally work on easier problems, providing in other ways the work that can advance a physicalist agenda.
We confessional Lutherans also have a problem that is so big that we really don't want to entertain it. We want to work on things that can be worked upon profitably, e.g,, Law/Gospel matters, not problems that seem intractable, problems that pertain to the truth of our theological position.
All the standard paths are open for the Lutheran wanting to talk about truth, of course. One could say that proposition p is true if and only if p describes or expresses the feelings, attitudes or the existential orientation of the one so uttering p. Or one might improve this somewhat by saying that p is true if and only if it liberates from sin and grants the freedom for the future (whatever precisely might by meant by "sin" and "freedom for the future" in this context). Or one might say that p is true if and only if it functions as a rule for the specification and use of other utterances by a particular linguistic community. Or perhaps one is less trendy and say that p is true if and only if p obtains. But then one must ask the rule specifying the condition for p obtaining.
Readers will understand that this last option asks that we think about the truth of p in broadly "cognitive-propositional" terms. For one stating that 'God was in Christ reconciling the world to Himself' is true if and only if God was in Christ reconciling the world to Himself, the question is what conditions must be met in order for God to be in Christ reconciling the world to Himself. This is not an easy question, as we shall see. One could say that that there is an individual God, and individual Christ, and that the two are related by the first being in the second. But this does not help too much either, for what are the conditions for "being in"?
At this point, the discussion of the last few decades about Christian inclusivism, exclusivism and pluralism becomes relevant. One could say that there is some kind of linguistic commensurability across religions such that the same objects and events can be in principle picked out in the various religious worlds. On this view, the Christin and Buddhist would presumably disagree about whether God was in Christ obtains, but they would both understand what it means. However, if a particular kind of holism holds, then the Buddhist could not state that "God was in Christ" in the same way as the Christian, and thus the fact that it obtains for one and not the other would not entail that the very same thing would need to obtain for both in order for truth to be predicated.
The point is a basic one between internalism and externalism. Are there conditions that must be met in order for a proposition to correctly apply to a situation, conditions that are internal to the proposition in question (and its relevant context), or are they external to it? What I am asking is simply whether or not there can be some "bird's eye" factual perspective above and beyond the practico-linguistic worlds occupied by adherents of the various world religions. While this question of the priority of facts over language arises within philosophy generally, theologians must pay especially intense attention to it because, in some sense, much of what the theologian is trying to talk about is beyond what can be said to be factual in any ordinary sense. The theologian who embraces externalism must seemingly hold, as John Hick suggests, to a view that Ultimate Referent of religious and theological language lies beyond the linguistic worlds of any religion and that it is a noumenal reality to which the phenomenal fields of meaning of the various traditions point.
Lutherans do not often enter the fray on what many would regard as a "philosophy of religion" concern, but it is simply the case that some position on the inclusivism, eclusivism, pluralism issue is more cogent and plausible than others, and must thereby be adopted - - either explicitly or implicitly. While the relationship between grace and nature in some of the Catholic theological tradition sets up nicely for inclusivist views like those of Rahner, Lutheran emphasis on the discontinuity between these two seem to block any argument for being an "anonymous Lutheran." A tendency towards exclusivism seems to be in the Lutheran theological DNA, but clearly we cannot easily argue like seventeenth century Lutherans did before the "Copernican revolution" of realizing that Christian faith is one belief system among the other world religions, and that the Lutheran take on Christianity does not predominate even there.
To hold to religious pluralism is much easier when one works with an alethia account of truth as unveiling, rather than an account that supposes there is an objective reality identified by Christians as the Triune God. To the theological realist, of course, truth is not promiscuous, and it is predicated of those propositions that tend to represent most accurately that which can never be known. (While the paradox here makes this problem seems acute, it is no worse than the problem of the external world generally.)
I believe that the big problem I describe here should be regarded as such by any Lutheran thinking through the options on the table. We cannot simply decide not to engage the issue. To do that would be an example of the quietism we have so long been accused of sponsoring.
For instance, biological properties distribute as a function of chemical properties, which distribute as a function of molecular properties, which themselves distribute as a function of atomic properties or subatomic properties. While there are some problems relating levels, the big problem concerns how it is that psychological properties covary with respect to neurophysiological properties.
While we may have no difficulties in general in countenancing a view of things where neurophysiological actualizations are finally metaphysically dependent upon mircrophysical causation, the notion that thoughts and decisions might ultimately metaphysically depend upon mircophysical processes is disquieting. While moderate reductions seem unproblematic throughout physical reality, the countenancing of reductions between the mental and physical involves some rather paradoxical claims, e.g., the notion that my writing these words in this blog right now themselves metaphysically depend somehow upon microphysical actualizations of various kinds.
While some philosophers here warmly embrace the "downward causality" of the mental into the physical on a mereological basis, the fundamental problem remains: If mental event m1 causes neurophysiological actualizations p2, then it seems that m1 must either itself have a physical realization or not. If it has no physical realization, then the advocate of downward causation must finally advocate a substance dualism - - something they want to avoid - - or she or he must admit that the physical realizer of m1 - - let us call this p1 -- itself causes p2, and there is no real downward causation. So the big problem is simply this: How is genuine freedom possible for an agent when the agent and his/her acts are metaphysically dependent upon microphysics? The problem is so big and intractable, that philosophers generally work on easier problems, providing in other ways the work that can advance a physicalist agenda.
We confessional Lutherans also have a problem that is so big that we really don't want to entertain it. We want to work on things that can be worked upon profitably, e.g,, Law/Gospel matters, not problems that seem intractable, problems that pertain to the truth of our theological position.
All the standard paths are open for the Lutheran wanting to talk about truth, of course. One could say that proposition p is true if and only if p describes or expresses the feelings, attitudes or the existential orientation of the one so uttering p. Or one might improve this somewhat by saying that p is true if and only if it liberates from sin and grants the freedom for the future (whatever precisely might by meant by "sin" and "freedom for the future" in this context). Or one might say that p is true if and only if it functions as a rule for the specification and use of other utterances by a particular linguistic community. Or perhaps one is less trendy and say that p is true if and only if p obtains. But then one must ask the rule specifying the condition for p obtaining.
Readers will understand that this last option asks that we think about the truth of p in broadly "cognitive-propositional" terms. For one stating that 'God was in Christ reconciling the world to Himself' is true if and only if God was in Christ reconciling the world to Himself, the question is what conditions must be met in order for God to be in Christ reconciling the world to Himself. This is not an easy question, as we shall see. One could say that that there is an individual God, and individual Christ, and that the two are related by the first being in the second. But this does not help too much either, for what are the conditions for "being in"?
At this point, the discussion of the last few decades about Christian inclusivism, exclusivism and pluralism becomes relevant. One could say that there is some kind of linguistic commensurability across religions such that the same objects and events can be in principle picked out in the various religious worlds. On this view, the Christin and Buddhist would presumably disagree about whether God was in Christ obtains, but they would both understand what it means. However, if a particular kind of holism holds, then the Buddhist could not state that "God was in Christ" in the same way as the Christian, and thus the fact that it obtains for one and not the other would not entail that the very same thing would need to obtain for both in order for truth to be predicated.
The point is a basic one between internalism and externalism. Are there conditions that must be met in order for a proposition to correctly apply to a situation, conditions that are internal to the proposition in question (and its relevant context), or are they external to it? What I am asking is simply whether or not there can be some "bird's eye" factual perspective above and beyond the practico-linguistic worlds occupied by adherents of the various world religions. While this question of the priority of facts over language arises within philosophy generally, theologians must pay especially intense attention to it because, in some sense, much of what the theologian is trying to talk about is beyond what can be said to be factual in any ordinary sense. The theologian who embraces externalism must seemingly hold, as John Hick suggests, to a view that Ultimate Referent of religious and theological language lies beyond the linguistic worlds of any religion and that it is a noumenal reality to which the phenomenal fields of meaning of the various traditions point.
Lutherans do not often enter the fray on what many would regard as a "philosophy of religion" concern, but it is simply the case that some position on the inclusivism, eclusivism, pluralism issue is more cogent and plausible than others, and must thereby be adopted - - either explicitly or implicitly. While the relationship between grace and nature in some of the Catholic theological tradition sets up nicely for inclusivist views like those of Rahner, Lutheran emphasis on the discontinuity between these two seem to block any argument for being an "anonymous Lutheran." A tendency towards exclusivism seems to be in the Lutheran theological DNA, but clearly we cannot easily argue like seventeenth century Lutherans did before the "Copernican revolution" of realizing that Christian faith is one belief system among the other world religions, and that the Lutheran take on Christianity does not predominate even there.
To hold to religious pluralism is much easier when one works with an alethia account of truth as unveiling, rather than an account that supposes there is an objective reality identified by Christians as the Triune God. To the theological realist, of course, truth is not promiscuous, and it is predicated of those propositions that tend to represent most accurately that which can never be known. (While the paradox here makes this problem seems acute, it is no worse than the problem of the external world generally.)
I believe that the big problem I describe here should be regarded as such by any Lutheran thinking through the options on the table. We cannot simply decide not to engage the issue. To do that would be an example of the quietism we have so long been accused of sponsoring.
Saturday, October 08, 2011
The Ugly Broad Ditch
Gotthold Ephriam Lessing (1729-81) is famous for a great many things, one being the authorship of the trenchant phrase, "the ugly broad ditch which I cannot get across."
Lessing's "broad ugly ditch" concerns the supposed jump Christian theology must make from the accidental truths of history to the necessary truths of reason. He writes: "If on historical grounds I have no objection to the statement that Christ raised to life a dead man; must I therefore accept it as true that God has a Son that is of the same essence as Himself?" Lessing's solution to the problem of the ugly broad ditch is not to base the deep truths of religion on the contingent facts of history, but rather to reverse the situation and find in history an exemplification of the deepest truths of religion. These truths are ultimately grounded not in history but in personal experience. Lessing compares his solution to geometry: "Is the situation such that 'I should hold a geometrical theorem to be true not because it can be demonstrated, but because it can be found in Euclid'?" The truths of Christianity are to history as the theorems of Euclid are to Euclid. History no more grounds Christian truth than Euclid grounds geometrical truth.
A distinction used among twentieth-century philosophers gets at the issue about which Lessing is concerned. We must distinguish the context of the origination of a putative truth from its context of justification. Just because probability theory originated among men of rather unsavory reputation playing in the Italian casinos does not mean that probability theory is somehow incorrect. Truth claims must be justified in the logical space of reason, not by an appeal to external historical circumstances. The context of origination (or discovery) of a truth simply is logically independent from the context of its justification. To confuse the two is to commit the genetic fallacy, to claim that an argument is unsound on the basis of the one giving it (and the purposes for which it is given), rather than on the basis of the evidence for the premises and the validity of the reasoning.
Lessing's claim is thus that the "ugly broad ditch" of logical independence separates the context of the origination of Christian truth from the context of its justification, and that this "ugly ditch" is, in effect, necessary to prevent one from committing the genetic fallacy. Christian truth must stand on its own legs; it must not be dependent upon who said what when. Reflecting a bit on this, one realizes that the problematic of the "ugly ditch" forces one to take a position on revelation: what is it for God to "disclose" to us truth that we could not have grasped by free exercise of our insight?
Specifically, we must inquire as to whether revelation is best conceived as external, contingent and accidental, or whether we might understand it to be somehow internal, necessary and reasonable? (I am using "necessary" here in the sense of Lessing, and not making a modal claim.) This question as to the "location" of revelation goes right to the heart of the matter, I believe, and how one answers it determines who one's theological comrades are and, indeed, even potentially what century one lives in theologically. For Lutheran Orthodoxy, there could be no question of the "place" of revelation. It is indeed external; the formal norm of Scripture establishes the material norm of Christ, and both norm theological reflection. For denizens of the heady world of nineteenth century post-Kantian theology, revelation's "place" cannot be external because there can in principle be no bridging of the ditch on that assumption. The contingency of the Biblical text, the contingency of history, the contingency of the Christian tradition all mitigate against a successful justification of the most profound truth of all of life.
Within Lutheran theology we have moved a very great distance indeed since the time of Lessing. We have passed through German idealism, the disintegration of Hegelianism into the right and left wing schools, the rise and fall the Ritschlian School, the rise of fall of Neo-Orthodoxy, existential, phenomenological and hermeneutical theological approaches, and the various theologies of liberation. We have witnessed sophisticated, learned attempts to do theology faithfully, attempts that understand the intellectual and cultural horizon of the time as well as the witness of Scripture and tradition. But the sophistication of the theological enterprise over the last two centuries can sometimes obfuscate certain fundamental questions. The question of the ontology of revelation is central among these questions. It infects all of our theological thinking, oftentimes confusing conversational partners to the point of not knowing even that they are confused! I will close this brief essay with an example of how this is so.
Lutherans have always spoken of sola scriptura, claiming that Christian truth is not founded on the pronouncements of canon law, councils or popes, or in the authority of the patristics or other church fathers. Authority is found in Scriptures. But now the question arises: In the meaning of the written words of Scripture? The standard reply here, of course, is "no!" The words of Scripture are themselves to be understood contextually both synchronically and diachronically. The words of Scripture have meaning within the context of their origination and throughout the context of their transmission, and in the context of Scripture itself being a tertiary witness to the primacy of the Word manifest in Christ and the secondary witness to this Word in the immediate oral tradition. Now this way of things has interesting corollaries because it makes it difficult to claim that unsophisticated readers can ever "know" what Scripture is meaning. (Presumably, one must know the context deeply before one can know the text.) One could simply ignore these problems, but one does it at one's own theological peril. Regardless, the larger problem of Lessing forever looms: Something in the contingencies of history and tradition can undermine Christian truth, the truth upon which our very existence rests.
So another way of understanding Scriptural authority must seemingly be sought, a way that does not abandon Scripture in externality, but which rather protects the sola scriptura from the vicissitudes of scholarship upon the text and context. This way of understanding, I think, must proceed by locating authority somehow immediately within the reading of the text. The text is not authoritative because of some historical, causal connection to a divine nexus, but is rather authoritative because of what it somehow does to the reader in its reading. The place of revelation is now found within the power of the revelatory event itself. The original authoritative externality of the sola is now translated safely into the inner authority of the event of revelation as text confronts reader.
It should be obvious that all of this has very deep repercussions for Lutherans fighting about whether the practice of homosexuality is consistent with Biblical truth. The relationship among the notions of Biblical authority, revelation, Christian truth, and the "ugly broad ditch" cannot be more palpable. It is not my intention here to offer a constructive solution to the problem, but merely point it out. I have always believed that if we could get clear on the problems in theology, perhaps we could get clear on the kinds of discussions that would profitably lead to a solution.
Lessing's "broad ugly ditch" concerns the supposed jump Christian theology must make from the accidental truths of history to the necessary truths of reason. He writes: "If on historical grounds I have no objection to the statement that Christ raised to life a dead man; must I therefore accept it as true that God has a Son that is of the same essence as Himself?" Lessing's solution to the problem of the ugly broad ditch is not to base the deep truths of religion on the contingent facts of history, but rather to reverse the situation and find in history an exemplification of the deepest truths of religion. These truths are ultimately grounded not in history but in personal experience. Lessing compares his solution to geometry: "Is the situation such that 'I should hold a geometrical theorem to be true not because it can be demonstrated, but because it can be found in Euclid'?" The truths of Christianity are to history as the theorems of Euclid are to Euclid. History no more grounds Christian truth than Euclid grounds geometrical truth.
A distinction used among twentieth-century philosophers gets at the issue about which Lessing is concerned. We must distinguish the context of the origination of a putative truth from its context of justification. Just because probability theory originated among men of rather unsavory reputation playing in the Italian casinos does not mean that probability theory is somehow incorrect. Truth claims must be justified in the logical space of reason, not by an appeal to external historical circumstances. The context of origination (or discovery) of a truth simply is logically independent from the context of its justification. To confuse the two is to commit the genetic fallacy, to claim that an argument is unsound on the basis of the one giving it (and the purposes for which it is given), rather than on the basis of the evidence for the premises and the validity of the reasoning.
Lessing's claim is thus that the "ugly broad ditch" of logical independence separates the context of the origination of Christian truth from the context of its justification, and that this "ugly ditch" is, in effect, necessary to prevent one from committing the genetic fallacy. Christian truth must stand on its own legs; it must not be dependent upon who said what when. Reflecting a bit on this, one realizes that the problematic of the "ugly ditch" forces one to take a position on revelation: what is it for God to "disclose" to us truth that we could not have grasped by free exercise of our insight?
Specifically, we must inquire as to whether revelation is best conceived as external, contingent and accidental, or whether we might understand it to be somehow internal, necessary and reasonable? (I am using "necessary" here in the sense of Lessing, and not making a modal claim.) This question as to the "location" of revelation goes right to the heart of the matter, I believe, and how one answers it determines who one's theological comrades are and, indeed, even potentially what century one lives in theologically. For Lutheran Orthodoxy, there could be no question of the "place" of revelation. It is indeed external; the formal norm of Scripture establishes the material norm of Christ, and both norm theological reflection. For denizens of the heady world of nineteenth century post-Kantian theology, revelation's "place" cannot be external because there can in principle be no bridging of the ditch on that assumption. The contingency of the Biblical text, the contingency of history, the contingency of the Christian tradition all mitigate against a successful justification of the most profound truth of all of life.
Within Lutheran theology we have moved a very great distance indeed since the time of Lessing. We have passed through German idealism, the disintegration of Hegelianism into the right and left wing schools, the rise and fall the Ritschlian School, the rise of fall of Neo-Orthodoxy, existential, phenomenological and hermeneutical theological approaches, and the various theologies of liberation. We have witnessed sophisticated, learned attempts to do theology faithfully, attempts that understand the intellectual and cultural horizon of the time as well as the witness of Scripture and tradition. But the sophistication of the theological enterprise over the last two centuries can sometimes obfuscate certain fundamental questions. The question of the ontology of revelation is central among these questions. It infects all of our theological thinking, oftentimes confusing conversational partners to the point of not knowing even that they are confused! I will close this brief essay with an example of how this is so.
Lutherans have always spoken of sola scriptura, claiming that Christian truth is not founded on the pronouncements of canon law, councils or popes, or in the authority of the patristics or other church fathers. Authority is found in Scriptures. But now the question arises: In the meaning of the written words of Scripture? The standard reply here, of course, is "no!" The words of Scripture are themselves to be understood contextually both synchronically and diachronically. The words of Scripture have meaning within the context of their origination and throughout the context of their transmission, and in the context of Scripture itself being a tertiary witness to the primacy of the Word manifest in Christ and the secondary witness to this Word in the immediate oral tradition. Now this way of things has interesting corollaries because it makes it difficult to claim that unsophisticated readers can ever "know" what Scripture is meaning. (Presumably, one must know the context deeply before one can know the text.) One could simply ignore these problems, but one does it at one's own theological peril. Regardless, the larger problem of Lessing forever looms: Something in the contingencies of history and tradition can undermine Christian truth, the truth upon which our very existence rests.
So another way of understanding Scriptural authority must seemingly be sought, a way that does not abandon Scripture in externality, but which rather protects the sola scriptura from the vicissitudes of scholarship upon the text and context. This way of understanding, I think, must proceed by locating authority somehow immediately within the reading of the text. The text is not authoritative because of some historical, causal connection to a divine nexus, but is rather authoritative because of what it somehow does to the reader in its reading. The place of revelation is now found within the power of the revelatory event itself. The original authoritative externality of the sola is now translated safely into the inner authority of the event of revelation as text confronts reader.
It should be obvious that all of this has very deep repercussions for Lutherans fighting about whether the practice of homosexuality is consistent with Biblical truth. The relationship among the notions of Biblical authority, revelation, Christian truth, and the "ugly broad ditch" cannot be more palpable. It is not my intention here to offer a constructive solution to the problem, but merely point it out. I have always believed that if we could get clear on the problems in theology, perhaps we could get clear on the kinds of discussions that would profitably lead to a solution.
Sunday, September 04, 2011
Can a Lutheran Semantics be Recovered?
For some time now I have been interested in theological semantics. Reading Wittgenstein's Tractatus thirty years ago, made me acutely aware of the problems we encounter when we try to talk about extra-worldly" things. (I include any talk about a talking about extra-worldly things as itself an extra-worldly thing.) Wittgenstein's distinction among propositions having Sinn (sense), those that are sinnlos (senseless), and those having nicht Sinn (nonsense), was for me very convincing that theology encounters significant problems in its speaking. Because I thought in those days that getting clear on semantics could be done independently from affirming or presupposing a metaphysic, I thought that there was some global problem with theological semantics. The language simply could not refer properly, it could not clearly affirm a state of affairs that one could falsify. Because I was hoping to become a theologian, the idea that the language of the trade was strictly speaking nonsense, caused me considerable discomfort.
While I am still somewhat uncomfortable with the general problem of theological language, over the the years I have gradually come to understand that a deep relationship exists between semantics and metaphysics and/or ontology. There simply are no semantic facts and judgments that can be made (or presupposed) independently of what one believes is that case. For the Wittgenstein of the Tractatus, a metaphysical atomism nicely accompanies his semantic nominalism. If it is true that facts comprise the world - - "Die Welt ist die Gesamtheit der Tatsache, nicht der Dingen - - and if there are not ethical, philosophical, aesthetic and theological facts, then the propositions purporting to talk about these things must be "pseudo-propositions." They look like they are making factual claims, but are finally not doing so.
Because of the press of many matters, I have not developed adequately what I regard to be the case: The Lutheran Reformers were unreflective theological realists and the presupposition of such a realism made them theological semantic realists as well. For those who wrote, read, debated, and signed the various confessional documents, there was simply no question that the language of the documents referred to divine entities, properties, events and states of affairs. Furthermore, because they believed that a divine realm exists outside of human awareness, perception, conception and language, the language could rather unproblematically connect to it, and state what is the case (or not the case) with respect to it. Confessions-talk is thus talk "in the material mode;" for the Reformers it made truth-claims of the world, for the world of the Reformers was filled with facts about which Wittgenstein would be astonished. His judgment that human language was unable to picture in logical space the transcendent was simply an admission of what philosophers since the Enlightenment presupposed: Talk of the divine was, in general, on very problematic epistemological footing.
This epistemic liability is related to ontology: One either says that we cannot affirm p because we cannot know that p is, or that we can affirm p even though we don't know for sure that p is - -or perhaps that our criterion of "for sure" has changed. In the Reformation period, when what it meant to know "for sure" was different than the Enlightenment, one could reasonably hold metaphysical facts that later became quite unreasonable. As it goes with metaphysics, so it goes with semantics. If it is unreasonable to hold a particular metaphysics, then it is reasonable to revise our language or, like Wittgenstein, claim that there is something about our natural language that makes it the case that it naturally can refer to states of affairs of a materialist or physicalist nature, but cannot picture a theological order at all.
We theologians who learned that the theological task must go through Kant learned to neglect certain questions and to prioritize others. The possibility of theological semantics (including theological truth) had to begin with a rejection of the very possibility of theological and semantic realism. Trained in the post-Kantian theological tradition, we looked at the texts of the Lutheran Confessions with quite different eyes than those who formulated, debated, and signed them. The questions that were of interest to us were naturally about things that could be of interest to us.
None of this is, of course, necessarilya bad thing. Classic texts have a deep fecundity; their history of interpretation takes them sometimes far from the contexts in which they are written. However, when the Churches of the Augsburg Confession find themselves no longer able deeply to recognize each other, then the question arises: When has the interpretation ceased any claim to normativity? How does one determine what is normative about such normativity in this case? Is there a set of presuppositions or affirmations that grounds a normative stance on the Confessions?
My sense is that Lutherans will continue to talk past each other as long as they are unwilling to articulate their ontologies. We live in a far different context than that of Wilhelm Hermann who claimed the independence of theological assertion from metaphysics. In a time where society and culture no longer grant a continuity of theological practice and expression (through a difference of ontological interpretation), people are searching again for authentic claims. They are not looking to find some way to justify the continued use of a theological language in the face of modern philosophical and scientific developments, but rather they search for a ground or reason to employ such language at all. As it was in the beginning of the Christian tradition, so it is now: The only reason to employ the language is that we Christians regard something to be true that non-Christians do not so regard. But the question of truth is always connected to the question of being. So it is that we Lutheran Christians must ask, "What is it that we hold to be so that others don't so hold, that is what it is apart from us, and that we sense the need to tell others about? What is this thing?
The Reformers could not have entertained this question without presupposing a rather explicit theological realism. The question for us is simply this: Can we? I used to think we could, but I no longer believe this. If Christ has not risen from the dead, than we Christians are the most to be pitied.
While I am still somewhat uncomfortable with the general problem of theological language, over the the years I have gradually come to understand that a deep relationship exists between semantics and metaphysics and/or ontology. There simply are no semantic facts and judgments that can be made (or presupposed) independently of what one believes is that case. For the Wittgenstein of the Tractatus, a metaphysical atomism nicely accompanies his semantic nominalism. If it is true that facts comprise the world - - "Die Welt ist die Gesamtheit der Tatsache, nicht der Dingen - - and if there are not ethical, philosophical, aesthetic and theological facts, then the propositions purporting to talk about these things must be "pseudo-propositions." They look like they are making factual claims, but are finally not doing so.
Because of the press of many matters, I have not developed adequately what I regard to be the case: The Lutheran Reformers were unreflective theological realists and the presupposition of such a realism made them theological semantic realists as well. For those who wrote, read, debated, and signed the various confessional documents, there was simply no question that the language of the documents referred to divine entities, properties, events and states of affairs. Furthermore, because they believed that a divine realm exists outside of human awareness, perception, conception and language, the language could rather unproblematically connect to it, and state what is the case (or not the case) with respect to it. Confessions-talk is thus talk "in the material mode;" for the Reformers it made truth-claims of the world, for the world of the Reformers was filled with facts about which Wittgenstein would be astonished. His judgment that human language was unable to picture in logical space the transcendent was simply an admission of what philosophers since the Enlightenment presupposed: Talk of the divine was, in general, on very problematic epistemological footing.
This epistemic liability is related to ontology: One either says that we cannot affirm p because we cannot know that p is, or that we can affirm p even though we don't know for sure that p is - -or perhaps that our criterion of "for sure" has changed. In the Reformation period, when what it meant to know "for sure" was different than the Enlightenment, one could reasonably hold metaphysical facts that later became quite unreasonable. As it goes with metaphysics, so it goes with semantics. If it is unreasonable to hold a particular metaphysics, then it is reasonable to revise our language or, like Wittgenstein, claim that there is something about our natural language that makes it the case that it naturally can refer to states of affairs of a materialist or physicalist nature, but cannot picture a theological order at all.
We theologians who learned that the theological task must go through Kant learned to neglect certain questions and to prioritize others. The possibility of theological semantics (including theological truth) had to begin with a rejection of the very possibility of theological and semantic realism. Trained in the post-Kantian theological tradition, we looked at the texts of the Lutheran Confessions with quite different eyes than those who formulated, debated, and signed them. The questions that were of interest to us were naturally about things that could be of interest to us.
None of this is, of course, necessarilya bad thing. Classic texts have a deep fecundity; their history of interpretation takes them sometimes far from the contexts in which they are written. However, when the Churches of the Augsburg Confession find themselves no longer able deeply to recognize each other, then the question arises: When has the interpretation ceased any claim to normativity? How does one determine what is normative about such normativity in this case? Is there a set of presuppositions or affirmations that grounds a normative stance on the Confessions?
My sense is that Lutherans will continue to talk past each other as long as they are unwilling to articulate their ontologies. We live in a far different context than that of Wilhelm Hermann who claimed the independence of theological assertion from metaphysics. In a time where society and culture no longer grant a continuity of theological practice and expression (through a difference of ontological interpretation), people are searching again for authentic claims. They are not looking to find some way to justify the continued use of a theological language in the face of modern philosophical and scientific developments, but rather they search for a ground or reason to employ such language at all. As it was in the beginning of the Christian tradition, so it is now: The only reason to employ the language is that we Christians regard something to be true that non-Christians do not so regard. But the question of truth is always connected to the question of being. So it is that we Lutheran Christians must ask, "What is it that we hold to be so that others don't so hold, that is what it is apart from us, and that we sense the need to tell others about? What is this thing?
The Reformers could not have entertained this question without presupposing a rather explicit theological realism. The question for us is simply this: Can we? I used to think we could, but I no longer believe this. If Christ has not risen from the dead, than we Christians are the most to be pitied.
Labels:
epistemology,
semantic realism,
semantics,
theological realism
Friday, July 01, 2011
Institute of Lutheran Theology Happenings
As many of you know, I have had the opportunity these last years to serve as the founding president of the Institute of Lutheran Theology. I have been grateful to have been able to do this. The time came a few months ago, however, for me to reevaluate what it is that I can do and can't do. With the Institute growing so quickly, it just is not possible any longer for me to serve both as President of ILT and Vice President of Academic Affairs. Accordingly, as of the June ILT Board meeting I am no longer president of this organization, but now VP of Academic Affairs only, I am very excited to be back doing mostly academic work, and am thrilled about the new person the ILT Board has selected to represent ILT as president. The announcement of this new person will come later this summer.
Many people connected with the Institute of Lutheran Theology have recently been contacted by a former staff person of ILT concerning a new start-up entitled "St. Paul Lutheran Seminary." As it turns out, two former staff members of ILT are advertising that a new seminary will be on-line this fall, and they have apparently gotten one former ILT faculty member to teach for them. Like the ILT Board and the rest of the ILT staff, I am concerned that people understand that "St. Paul Lutheran Seminary" is in no way connected to ILT. Its efforts are neither supported nor sanctioned by ILT.
Now the question arises: What motivation might there be to start a new seminary? It seems that when things like this happen within Lutheran circles, there are generally the following motivations:
One might start a new seminary because of theological reasons. However, it appears that the new entity has no theological differences with ILT. The Institute has always tried to understand Lutheran theology in the context of its origination and development, and related this theology to the contemporary intellectual horizon. I doubt if the new organization is opposed to this.
One might start a new seminary because of ecclesioloigical reasons. However, it appears that the new entity is striving to serve the same market as ILT. The Institute has always tried to serve LCMC and NALC congregations, and support as well those ELCA congregations who sense they are not being fed theologically by the ELCA seminaries.
One might start a new seminary because of structural/organizational reasons. However, it appears that the organization of ILT as a "distributed residential community" with non-geographic "Designated Teaching Centers" using the latest in synchronous technology is one with which the new entity might agree.
Sometimes it is said that if one puts three Lutherans in the same room, one gets three different theological traditions. Lutherans have traditionally privileged truth over unity. When important doctrinal/theological issues are at stake, Lutherans have historically separated from one another. However, Lutherans need not be opposed to unity. We can work together. Sometimes unity is a very good thing. ILT has always hoped that one seminary might develop to be the voice of theological conscience within present day Lutheran diaspora. I do not think the present context warrants a division or reduplication of efforts in the building of a truly confessional Lutheran seminary.
I have been working on trying to build ILT for about six years now. We have now a very fine faculty, scores of students, a great curriculum, dozens of congregations relating closely to us, and the financial stability to accomplish those things we believe that God has put before us. The future is very exciting! Let us work together in trust and love.
Soli deo gloria.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)