Immanuel Kant employs transcendental logic to show that the synthesis involved in judging that the conceptual "presentation" (Vorstellung) P applying to the conceptual "presentation" (Vorstellung) S also applies to intuitional presentations (Vorstellungen). In other words, the syntheses involved in the act of judgment in general ultimately make possible the world of our experience, a world in which we know objects.
According to Kant, while general logic abstracts from the particular content of concepts related, concentrating instead on the formal features involved in relating the concepts, transcendental logic deals with the most general features of our experience of objects in space and time. Unlike general logic, transcendental logic is not about the capacity for thinking as such, but concerns itself with our thinking in relation to our experience of objects as such. Accordingly, transcendental logic deals with rules of synthesis in so far as this synthesis applies to intuitions as well as to concepts. It is left to Kant's transcendental deduction to show that the necessary condition for the possibility of experience as such is that there exists a transcendental unity of apperception, an "I think" that is presupposed in all activity of knowing objects.
Kant famously offers a transcendental deduction in the first edition of the Critique -- the "A deduction" -- which he completely rewrites in the second edition six years later -- the "B deduction." There is a pronounced difference in emphasis between the two deductions with the first being predominantly a "subjective deduction" while the second attempts an "objective deduction."
The precise contour of the transcendental arguments are a matter of considerable debate, but one might broadly paint the "B deduction" as follows:
- Our experience is one of a succession of awarenesses, that is, a succession of contents of consciousness.
- The condition for a succession of awarenesses, however, is an awareness of the succession itself, that is, the successive contents of consciousness must be combined and held together in a unity of consciousness. Such a unity is a necessary condition for an experience of succession.
- For this synthesis to be presented (represented), I must think it.
- But this analytic unity of the self thinking its objects presupposes a synthetic unity of the manifold. In other words, presupposed is a transcendental unity of apperception, a unity of the "I think" that is neither the empirical "self" of psychology, nor a metaphysical thinking substance a la Descartes. (The "I" could never know itself if it were not possible to unify the manifold through synthesis.)
- The transcendental unity of apperception is an objective, not a subjective, unity. The conditions for this unity are the conditions by which we have consciousness of objects in general.
- An object is that under the concept of which the manifold is united. The necessary conditions for uniting the manifold is a unity of consciousness, a unity that bestows objective affinity to transcendental apperception.
- Since there is an objective unity in the transcendental unity of apperception, the synthesis must proceed according to the categories and the rules required for experience as such.
- Premise I: There is the possibility of experience as such. Using Polish notation of L for the necessity operation and M for the possibility operator, we might say 'Me', experience is possible.
- Premise II: It is necessary that, if experience is possible, then there exist conditions C for that experience. We might express this as 'L, if Me, then o'. (I am using 'o' for 'conditions'.)
- Conclusion: Lo.
- We might have a system that might allow us to move from necessity to possibility. Using Polish notation, we have the distinguishing axiom 'CLpMp', if p is necessary, then p is possible. (Read the 'C' as the conditional 'if, then', e.g., 'if Lp, then Mp'.) That is, if p obtains in all possible worlds, p obtains in some possible world. (It is hard to conceive how something appearing in all possible world is not possible, for it is in every world that is, by definition, possible.)
- We could add to this first system another axiom this one from actuality to possibility: 'CpMp', if p obtains then p is possible. That is to say, if p obtains in the actual world, then p obtains in a possible world. (This seems plausible since the actual world is a possible world.)
- We can add to this second system another plausible theorem: 'CMMpMp'. We have now arrived at Lewis' system S4 holding that if something is possibly possible, then it is possible. In other words, if p is possible in a possible world, then p is itself in a possible world. (This seems plausible since all there are are possible worlds, and it would be strange were something possible in a possible world to somehow not simply be possible.)
- Finally, we get to S5, sometimes assumed to be the "standard" system of model logic. This system is generated from 'CLpMp', 'CpMp', CMMpMp' and the distinguishing assumptions of S5, 'CMLpLp', that is, if it is possible that something is necessary, then it is necessary. Simply put, if there is possible world where some necessity holds, then, since for something to be necessary it obtains in all possible worlds, that which is necessary in that possible world is now ingredient in every possible world. (It is hard to see what being necessary in a possible world might be, if that necessity does not extend over all possible worlds.)
- Premise I: Me
- Premise II: LCMeo (This says that necessarily, if possibly e then o.)
- S5 Assumption: CMLpLp
- But (2) is logically equivalent in all modal systems to 'CLMeLo'
- From(3), 'C~Lp~MLp'.
- (5) is equivalent to 'CM~pLM~p'.
- Substituting 'e' for '~p' uniformly, we get, 'CMeLMe'.
- Thus from (1), we derive 'LMe'.
- Now by (4) through modus ponens we get 'Lo', and thus 'o' constituted necessary conditions for the possibility of 'e'. QED.