It was regular practice in the medieval university for faculty and students to engage in the art of disputation. This blog presupposes the corporate nature of the theological enterprise, supposing that theology, particularly Lutheran theology, can once again clarify its truth claims and provide rational justification for its positions.
Showing posts with label truth. Show all posts
Showing posts with label truth. Show all posts
Thursday, November 15, 2018
Indeterminate Realism versus Phenomenological Ontology
We received word late yesterday (November 15, 2018) from our accrediting agency that we could begin offering our Ph.D. at the Institute of Lutheran theology in the fall of 2019. As the founding President of the Institute of Lutheran Theology (ILT), and having taken it from its early very tenuous years through accreditation, and now to this milestone, I wish to express my sincere thanks to all who have worked so diligently on this project. We have always done what we do to the glory of God, because the search for truth is its own reward.
I wrote this reflection earlier this week, and offer it up now in the spirit of truth. Clearly, blog writing is not meant to be scholarly writing with citations like one would find in a academic journal. That being said, I do think all I say below can be supported by the appropriate texts. As always, I am interested in any responses you might want to share on the blog.
________________________________________
I remember once having a rather protracted discussion with Langdon Gilkey (1919-2004) in a Des Moines church basement sometime around 1994. At that time, he would have been 75 years old. Like many, I had read Naming the Whirlwind in the early1970s, and had been impressed with the issues Langdon had raised on the future possibility of God-talk. Gilkey had given a talk reflecting on his teacher Paul Tillich that night in the church basement, and I wanted to talk to him about how I was understanding Tillich in those days.
Paul Tillich (1885-1965) wrote a number of widely-read books in the 1950s, including two that I regularly taught undergraduates, The Dynamics of Faith (1956) and The Courage to Be (1952). (I never had undergraduates read his Systematic Theology.) In both of those texts, Tillich had employed the notion of the "Ground of Being" in tandem with the "Power of Being," and the "depth of Being," distinguishing them all in The Dynamics of Faith from the "Structure of Being."
The Ground of Being, for Tillich in the 1950s, was the source of existential empowerment in the face of the fundamental anxieties of existence, the anxiety of fate and death, the anxiety of guilt and condemnation, and the anxiety of emptiness and meaninglessness. In those days, I admit to thinking that Tillich was committed to a phenomenological ontology, and that the Ground of Being simply could not be any "thing" at all. It was both Ground and Abyss, the Depth of Being whose function it was to be pointed to by religious symbols, and which somehow provided the "courage to be in spite of the fact of non-being," that is, that "negation of the negation of being" that provided being (through courage) existentially in the face of the non-being of existential anxiety. Whereas a phenomenological ontology could describe the structure of being, it could only point to that indeterminate reservoir of empowerment potential transcending that structure.
I remember talking to Langdon about this, trying to gauge what, in fact, Tillich's view on the Ground of Being was. I thought that perhaps Tillich himself knew that his phenomenological ontology pointed to a Ground of Being that could only be in and for consciousness, that as the reservoir of empowerment, it could not in any way be what it is apart from consciousness. In other words, I thought that Tillich would have to hold that if consciousness were not present, the Ground of Being could not exist either. I remember Gilkey listening earnestly to me and saying, "I think Tillich would never think of the Ground of Being in that way. After all, the Ground of Being for Paul was a real thing." He then said to me, "if you want to understand what Paul was talking about, you have to read Schelling." Since reading Schelling seriously was not then on my immediate to-do list, I admit to continuing to think that Tillich must finally be understood in the lineage of Martin Heidegger. Surely, his thought was not somehow indebted to one of Schelling's Five Systems. Was he not better understood as a thinker of his own age -- at least when he was thinking clearly like he was surely doing in the last 15 years of his life?
I have been talking about realism in theology these last years because I have thought profoundly important this claim: A thing is real if and only if that thing exists apart from human awareness, perception, conception and language. Applied to God, this is the claim that God is not real unless God's existence is what it is apart from human existence, that is to say, if and only if the existence of human beings is logically independent of God's existence. It thus seemed that one would have to adopt irrealism in theology if one were to ground one's theology in a phenomenological ontology. Irrealism is the simple denial of realism, the assertion that "it is not the case that God exists apart from human awareness, perception, conception and language."
It had been clear to me for some time that that if theology was going to be about something important, i.e., about that which the tradition had assumed it was about, it would have to make causal claims about salvation, claims of the type that "X would not have been saved -- however one construes this -- apart from the real existence and action of God." If Bob's existential empowerment could have occurred even were it not the case that the Ground of Being existed apart from human awareness, perception, conception and language, then it could not rightly be claimed that this salvific empowerment was caused by God. One might claim it was caused by some aspect of us, some depth of our own being with which we are not normally in contact.
It has also seemed to me for a very long time that God cannot be God if God were only a metaphysical absolute. The God that is the God of Christianity is tied to action, I thought, to acting so as aid God's children, to, as Tillich might say, "negate the negations of being."
This being said, ground of being theologies do have great metaphysical appeal. Wesley Wildman rightly points to their fascination: "They deny that ultimate reality is a determinate entity, and they deny that the universe is ontologically self-explanatory" (See "Ground-of-Being Theologies," in the Oxford Handbook of Religion and Science). My opinion is, however, that while the metaphysical absolute can be intellectually satisfying in myriad ways, if there is no salvific causal connection or metaphysical dependency relation that can be drawn from the Ground of Being to possible human transformation, then Ground of Being ontologies are not really helpful for the religious quest.
As I was thinking about the development of post-Kantian options for theology in the nineteenth century and into the twentieth century, I became quite uneasy with many of the moves, because they seemed mostly to be consistent with theological irrealism. What difference would it even make if there were a God that exists apart from human awareness, perception, conception and language if empowerment in the face of the fundamental existential anxieties did not even involve God? What difference would it make were there to exist a God that was soteriologically inert? God could, after all, have abstract existence, perhaps like the set of all ordered pairs, but if God were not related to the universe or people in it such that if God had not existed the salvific options of people would not be different, then in what sense is it even important to say that God is?
As an instance of possible irrealism, consider how it is possible that one can preach Law and Gospel, and deliver Christ in the sermon so that the grace of God is delivered in the forgiveness of sins without assuming the existence of God at all. If one presupposes a phenomenological ontology, the forgiveness proclaimed and received in the Word can be understood in terms of a change in the ontological linguisticallity of existence. If what it is to be is to be in a world in which one dwells in relationship to beings and values, then a linguistic event like preaching really can change one's world. One perhaps is donated a being-in-the-world which would not have happened apart from the event of preaching. The effects on the reader of Scripture, the hearer of the sermon, and the recipient of the sacrament could clearly be interpreted as not involving the action of some divine being. If language itself is performative and the linguistic event empowers, then why assert some other being, disconnected from the event whose action would vouchsafe for the success of the event's reception?
But what if Langdon Gilkey is right about Tillich, and that I really should have studied more deeply Schelling, or perhaps the later works of Kant whom Fichte and Schelling wholly devoured? While I have spent quite a bit of time in both The Critique of Pure Reason and The Critique of Practical Reason, I have never spent sufficient time with The Critique of Judgment, Kant's last great work of 1790. I have lately decided to read the work closely, and I now see how and why it was that both Fichte, Schelling, as well as a whole host of other philosophers, believed that Kant's greatest work was, in fact, the Critique of Judgment. The Critique of Pure Reason is very important, of course, but the options for philosophical and theological development from that work in an age threatened by mechanism were understandably limited. However, the Critique of Judgment with its emphasis on aesthetics and purpose seemed extremely relevant to the challenges of the early 19th century: How can one find unity, purpose and meaning in a natural universe in which everything that happens seems to be the result of some congeries or concatenation of events antecedently occurring?
In the Critique of Judgment, Kant attempts to find a linkage between the mechanism resulting from the understanding's theoretical cognition of nature and freedom resulting from practical cognition of the power of desire. The problem is the apparent antinomy between the assertion that all natural events are necessarily determined by other natural events and the claim that there are some events which are natural that are nonetheless not wholly determined by other natural events. After all, when confronted by the decision to either go to the party of stay home, Molly is immediately aware of her freedom not to go as the very presupposition for her thinking that she ought not to go party. Molly is a being in the world who is caused to behave as she does by her antecedent conditioning, but who nonetheless has the freedom to do other that what she did do. But how can all natural events have a cause in nature, when Molly is a natural being involved in natural events and she sometimes acts in ways seemingly determined by no natural events at all? How is the freedom of a human being, whose being is embodied in nature, possible?
Kant attempts to solve this antinomy by arguing that nature deals only with appearances, and so the appearance of determinism is not in conflict with the underlying freedom encountered in practical reason's grasp of its own duty. The freedom encountered by the reason in its moral life is not a freedom, however, solely resting in the subject. It is a freedom determined by reason's grasp of the supersensible substrate that exists both inside and outside the subject, a supersensible substrate that is indeterminate in itself, but is determined in moral experience. For Kant, however, there is a power of judgment which operates to make determinable the indeterminate supersensible subtrate, a determinability that is possible on the side of the object, that is, a determinability applicable to the entire supersensible substrate, not just that encountered by the subject.
In an important section of the Critique of Judgment, Kant argues that the transcendental notion of purpose applied to nature is finally no mere thinking of purpose on the side of the subject when thinking nature, a thinking that would be the subject's imposition of purpose upon nature, but it is a thinking itself grounded in the indeterminate supersensible substrate, a real supersensible substrate which is what it is, and in the application of judgment to it, can allow the thinking of purpose in nature.
It is impossible, of course, to think what is indeterminate, however, Kant does laud Judgment's ability to think the world as if it were designed by God and as if this God had placed the human effort towards fulfillment of the moral law as the highest good of this creation. While Kant knows that he cannot argue metaphysically for the real existence of this God without running into the antinomies, he does realize that human beings are allowed to think of the world of nature as if it is the result of objective purpose built into it by God, an objective purpose designed by God allowable on the basis or ground (Grund) of the supersensible substrate. This substrate cannot be thought for there are no universals under which any supersensible intuitions might fall. It is not able to be articulated by human beings, but it itself is that upon which analogies arise, analogies that allow human beings to think of nature as the field of moral activity without at the same time having to deny the results of the First Critique.
What does all of this mean? Well maybe Ground of Being theologies yet hold some hope if we can connect them to a Kantian supersensible substrate. If the Ground of Being underlying the Structure of Being is the supersensible substrate, an indeterminate noumenality that is the real reservoir of a power of being at the depth of being, a real reservoir of empowerment potential that can truly address the anxieties of fate and death, guilt and condemnation, and emptiness and meaninglessness, then perhaps we can read the entire tradition of theology based upon Kant a bit differently. There would be, after all, a God, and that God would do stuff. Its upon that God's basis that we could proclaim that God was indeed in Christ reconciling the world unto Himself. It is upon that Ground that the grace of Jesus Christ would be proclaimed and it is upon that really existing being that we could proclaim forgiveness and witness transformed lives. It is upon that Ground that the Spirit would blow when and where it wills, and that the play of the Trinitarian persons could be entertained. It is upon that Ground of divine simplicity that we could think the great thoughts of the Trinitarian tradition, a Ground deeper than substance but which is the true cause (Grund) of all that is. Maybe such an indeterminate realism is what the apophantic tradition was after all along.
Sunday, December 17, 2017
Tolerance, Commitment and the Lutheran Ethos
Forty years ago when I was farming in northwest Iowa, a farmer friend announced that the famous University of Chicago religion scholar Martin Marty was going to be speaking seventy miles away in Orange City, and he wondered if we might not want to go and hear him. Although I had not heard of Martin Marty back then, I could not pass up the opportunity to go to Orange City. As I recall, Marty was speaking on the general theme of tolerance and commitment, and telling us that mature faith possesses both. My friend Doug challenged professor Marty after the lecture: "Dr. Marty, I found your presentation very stimulating, but remain unconvinced. My own observations suggest that the more committed people are religiously the less tolerant they are, and the more tolerant they are, the less committed they are."
I recall that Martin Marty looked at my friend rather sadly, as if Doug had showed up for card night without knowing how to play. "That is not the way it works," he reiterated, "it is precisely in tolerance that one is most deeply committed." He uttered many other wise things as well, but I don't recall how anything he said provided warrant for the widely-propagated view that religious tolerance and commitment are profoundly compatible.
Of course, being good Americans in the early twenty-first century, most of us naturally pay lip-service not only to the compatibility of tolerance and commitment, but also to their direct direct proportionality. We Americans love our story. After all, America was founded on religious freedom, a freedom from compulsion to a particular religion so that one had greater freedom to practice one's chosen religion.
It was a great experiment, this founding of America. Could a country endure that tolerated many different religions, that rejected the assumption of the 1648 Peace of Westphalia: cuius regio, eius religio ("whose realm, his religion")? If Tillich is right and religion pertains to ultimate concern, then how is it possible for people with different -- sometimes radically different -- ultimate concerns to come together and agree to be governed? Far better, it would seem, the traditional view where the ruler and the ruled share the same ultimate commitment. But America not only survived, it thrived. Apparently people with different ultimate concerns can live together without compromising those concerns! So it is that we learn in America that it is precisely within the context of overarching tolerance that commitment is most deeply possible.
I remember thinking at the time, however, that Doug's question was a good one, and that the famed Dr. Marty had taken it rather too lightly. (We often underestimate the strength of challenges to our assumptions.) Perhaps Martin Marty was living so deeply in his religious tradition that he did not see the problem. How exactly does one continue to assert the truth of one's own tradition, allow others to assert the truth of their own, and not run into fundamental conflict? How does one do this if the truth about which one is concerned is ultimate?
My days on the farm was a time in my life that I was very interested in the question of religious truth. I puzzled a great deal over the question of how two or more religions might be true at the same time. I was a pretty tolerant guy in those days, and it did not come naturally to me to think that my Lutheran truth-claims were mostly all true, and those of Hindus, Buddhists, and Muslims almost all false. Why would I be given the requisite epistemic priority to know the true, when those far more serious than I were not afforded the same?
So assuming that contrary religious claims might be conjointly true, what would it be by virtue of which they could be conjointly true? While I was thinking such thoughts in 1978, I admit I did not know anyone in my farming community except Doug who thought that supposed contrary statements about God's properties and relations could somehow be conjointly true. Every Lutheran I knew thought that either God created the universe in six days or did not do so, that either Jesus was born of a virgin or was not so born, and that either Jesus the Christ was the only way to the Father or was not the only way.
Later in my life I would ask undergraduate students this question: "If two people disagree on what is true, must one of them be wrong?" In the middle 1980s when I started my college teaching career most students said "yes," but by 2010 when I was finishing my tenure of university teaching they were saying, "no." Perhaps in the 1980s the few students saying "no" were thinking about philosophical or religious "truth." (Just as beauty is in the eye of the beholder in aesthetics, truth is in the mind of the conceiver in philosophy or theology.) However, by 2010 students were assuming a much more expansive domain of putative truths, a domain that included the historical, scientific and even the mathematical. Be that as it may, if my college students in the late 1980s could think that contrary religious claims might be conjointly true, perhaps it was possible in a northwest Iowa farming community a decade earlier.
There are two ways, I believe, of conceiving the relationship between tolerance and commitment. The first is one that the American founding fathers could embrace. One must be tolerant of contrary claims in areas where one's epistemic limitations are the most pronounced. Since one cannot know that 'x is true', one must be tolerant of those claiming, 'it is false that x is true'. Such epistemic tolerance, however, is thoroughly compatible with the belief that 'x is true'. One can be deeply committed to the truth of a claim without knowing that the belief is true. Epistemic tolerance of x is clearly compatible with an existential commitment to ~x. Accordingly, tolerance of another's claims of truth is the proper attitude to adopt when realizing one's epistemic limitations, but commitment to one's own beliefs is, however, proper, honorable and courageous. After all, not to be committed to one's own beliefs is to live inauthentically, is to live in a way that does not own one's beliefs. (I am thinking of Heidegger's Eigenlichtkeit or "ownmostness.")
Doug and Dr. Marty would not, however, likely have affirmed this relatively traditional interpretation of the compatibility of tolerance and commitment. Both were quite aware of the intellectual and cultural horizon of the 1970s, a horizon that increasingly understood religious assertions as statements of value and not of fact. Accordingly, tolerance in things religious is assured because there is no way in principle for religious language to state what is the case apart from human awareness, perception, conception and language, and thus there is no facile way for its claims to come into conflict. Religious language (and most theological language) reports, expresses or recommends one's own psychological or existential states; it does not describe a divine realm existing on its own apart from us. Since such language pertains to human experience, every attempt to state that another's religious affirmations are false is an act of prejudice. Who can rightly say that my religious affirmations, grounded as they are in my experience, are false? If beauty is in the eye of the beholder, so too must the truths of religion be only in the ears and eyes of its hearers and readers.
Unfortunately, this view of things, though great for tolerance, presents deep problems for commitment. If I know that my affirmation of x is a statement of value, and I know that your affirmation of ~x is a statement of value, then since values are neither true nor false, upon what grounds can one be rightly committed to to x rather than ~x? Lamentably, the search for grounds for values succeeds only in uncovering other values. (No matter how hard I have tried, I have never been able to derive an "ought" from an "is.") Are not the deep values of the grounds simply another statement of commitment? (I am committed to feeding the hungry because I value -- I am committed to -- feeding the hungry.)
Simply put, if the warranted assertibility of religious utterances is ultimately subjective, then why be committed to the particularity of their assertion when times become difficult? While one might die for truth, does one really die for value? (I am not saying that one might not die for the truth of a value.) Polycarp (69-155) was burned alive rather than renounce faith in Christ. Clearly, the great man died because he was convinced of the truth of Christ, not the value Christ had for him.
Doug's question was sophisticated in the way of the medieval question of whether or not God could make a rock so heavy that He could not lift it. Doug was asking this: If one is tolerant in one's religious assertions, then one is clandestinely understanding these assertions as not have truth-conditions. But why be committed to the assertion of a particular body of statements or the doing of a set of actions if there are no truth-conditions grounding the assertion of the statements or the doing of the actions? Alternately, if one is committed to a set of assertions or a class of actions, then one is presupposing their truth, but if this is so then why be deeply tolerant of unjustified views at odds with those that one has good reason to regard as true? Just as the property of making a rock so heavy that God can't lift it cannot properly be applied to God, so to the property of being deeply tolerant of contrary religious claims while be profoundly committed to one's own cannot properly be applied to late twentieth-century Christian believers, those no longer believing as did the Founding Fathers that tolerance pertains to epistemic humility with regard to the domain of religious fact.
Dominant strands of Lutheran theology over the past 200 years have tended to downplay the idea that there exists a realm of theological facts independent of human awareness, perception, conception and language. Kantian assumptions within theology departments at German universities undercut notions of divine substantiality and causality. As European Lutheran theology hit American shores (particularly after World War II), and comingled with American assumptions about the fact/value distinction, a Lutheran theological ethos emerged that was disdainful of Lutheran Orthodoxy, particularly it's penchant to regard confessional and doctrinal statements as affirmations of theological fact. The result was heightened tensions among Lutherans, a tension pertaining to both semantics and ontology.
While conservative traditions like the Missouri and Wisconsin Synods continued to assume that there was some objective fact of the matter about which confessional and doctrinal statements were speaking truly, the precursor church bodies which became the ELCA began leaning towards an understanding of such language that connected more to human experience. While the former thus understood tolerance as grounded in epistemic limitation, the latter came to see it as an affirmation of the particularity of the believer's cultural existence itself. Tensions ran high, and it did not help when spokesman of the former sometimes suggested that the tolerance of epistemic humility was due to a willful abandonment of the objectivity of revelation. Nor were tensions abated when the latter seemed to think that confessional and doctrinal affirmations somehow denied the authenticity of the theologian or preacher's voice, and that such affirmations simply strangled the believer's authentic religious life and practice.
The Institute of Lutheran Theology emerged, in part, because it became time for there to be an institution that was both deeply sympathetic to the starting points of the various Lutheran traditions, and that understood these starting points within the broader historical and philosophical context. It is time now that Lutherans talk seriously to each other. It is time we think together the dialectic of tolerance and commitment, time we ask together how an affirmation of both is possible. In so asking, we shall undoubtedly learn a great deal more about ourselves. Such learning is a very good thing, for it is time that we dialogue with each other in a spirit of tolerance and commitment, a spirit that shall take the truth claims of all partners seriously, while adjudicating conflicting truth claims within an ethos of epistemic humility.
I recall that Martin Marty looked at my friend rather sadly, as if Doug had showed up for card night without knowing how to play. "That is not the way it works," he reiterated, "it is precisely in tolerance that one is most deeply committed." He uttered many other wise things as well, but I don't recall how anything he said provided warrant for the widely-propagated view that religious tolerance and commitment are profoundly compatible.
Of course, being good Americans in the early twenty-first century, most of us naturally pay lip-service not only to the compatibility of tolerance and commitment, but also to their direct direct proportionality. We Americans love our story. After all, America was founded on religious freedom, a freedom from compulsion to a particular religion so that one had greater freedom to practice one's chosen religion.
It was a great experiment, this founding of America. Could a country endure that tolerated many different religions, that rejected the assumption of the 1648 Peace of Westphalia: cuius regio, eius religio ("whose realm, his religion")? If Tillich is right and religion pertains to ultimate concern, then how is it possible for people with different -- sometimes radically different -- ultimate concerns to come together and agree to be governed? Far better, it would seem, the traditional view where the ruler and the ruled share the same ultimate commitment. But America not only survived, it thrived. Apparently people with different ultimate concerns can live together without compromising those concerns! So it is that we learn in America that it is precisely within the context of overarching tolerance that commitment is most deeply possible.
I remember thinking at the time, however, that Doug's question was a good one, and that the famed Dr. Marty had taken it rather too lightly. (We often underestimate the strength of challenges to our assumptions.) Perhaps Martin Marty was living so deeply in his religious tradition that he did not see the problem. How exactly does one continue to assert the truth of one's own tradition, allow others to assert the truth of their own, and not run into fundamental conflict? How does one do this if the truth about which one is concerned is ultimate?
My days on the farm was a time in my life that I was very interested in the question of religious truth. I puzzled a great deal over the question of how two or more religions might be true at the same time. I was a pretty tolerant guy in those days, and it did not come naturally to me to think that my Lutheran truth-claims were mostly all true, and those of Hindus, Buddhists, and Muslims almost all false. Why would I be given the requisite epistemic priority to know the true, when those far more serious than I were not afforded the same?
So assuming that contrary religious claims might be conjointly true, what would it be by virtue of which they could be conjointly true? While I was thinking such thoughts in 1978, I admit I did not know anyone in my farming community except Doug who thought that supposed contrary statements about God's properties and relations could somehow be conjointly true. Every Lutheran I knew thought that either God created the universe in six days or did not do so, that either Jesus was born of a virgin or was not so born, and that either Jesus the Christ was the only way to the Father or was not the only way.
Later in my life I would ask undergraduate students this question: "If two people disagree on what is true, must one of them be wrong?" In the middle 1980s when I started my college teaching career most students said "yes," but by 2010 when I was finishing my tenure of university teaching they were saying, "no." Perhaps in the 1980s the few students saying "no" were thinking about philosophical or religious "truth." (Just as beauty is in the eye of the beholder in aesthetics, truth is in the mind of the conceiver in philosophy or theology.) However, by 2010 students were assuming a much more expansive domain of putative truths, a domain that included the historical, scientific and even the mathematical. Be that as it may, if my college students in the late 1980s could think that contrary religious claims might be conjointly true, perhaps it was possible in a northwest Iowa farming community a decade earlier.
There are two ways, I believe, of conceiving the relationship between tolerance and commitment. The first is one that the American founding fathers could embrace. One must be tolerant of contrary claims in areas where one's epistemic limitations are the most pronounced. Since one cannot know that 'x is true', one must be tolerant of those claiming, 'it is false that x is true'. Such epistemic tolerance, however, is thoroughly compatible with the belief that 'x is true'. One can be deeply committed to the truth of a claim without knowing that the belief is true. Epistemic tolerance of x is clearly compatible with an existential commitment to ~x. Accordingly, tolerance of another's claims of truth is the proper attitude to adopt when realizing one's epistemic limitations, but commitment to one's own beliefs is, however, proper, honorable and courageous. After all, not to be committed to one's own beliefs is to live inauthentically, is to live in a way that does not own one's beliefs. (I am thinking of Heidegger's Eigenlichtkeit or "ownmostness.")
Doug and Dr. Marty would not, however, likely have affirmed this relatively traditional interpretation of the compatibility of tolerance and commitment. Both were quite aware of the intellectual and cultural horizon of the 1970s, a horizon that increasingly understood religious assertions as statements of value and not of fact. Accordingly, tolerance in things religious is assured because there is no way in principle for religious language to state what is the case apart from human awareness, perception, conception and language, and thus there is no facile way for its claims to come into conflict. Religious language (and most theological language) reports, expresses or recommends one's own psychological or existential states; it does not describe a divine realm existing on its own apart from us. Since such language pertains to human experience, every attempt to state that another's religious affirmations are false is an act of prejudice. Who can rightly say that my religious affirmations, grounded as they are in my experience, are false? If beauty is in the eye of the beholder, so too must the truths of religion be only in the ears and eyes of its hearers and readers.
Unfortunately, this view of things, though great for tolerance, presents deep problems for commitment. If I know that my affirmation of x is a statement of value, and I know that your affirmation of ~x is a statement of value, then since values are neither true nor false, upon what grounds can one be rightly committed to to x rather than ~x? Lamentably, the search for grounds for values succeeds only in uncovering other values. (No matter how hard I have tried, I have never been able to derive an "ought" from an "is.") Are not the deep values of the grounds simply another statement of commitment? (I am committed to feeding the hungry because I value -- I am committed to -- feeding the hungry.)
Simply put, if the warranted assertibility of religious utterances is ultimately subjective, then why be committed to the particularity of their assertion when times become difficult? While one might die for truth, does one really die for value? (I am not saying that one might not die for the truth of a value.) Polycarp (69-155) was burned alive rather than renounce faith in Christ. Clearly, the great man died because he was convinced of the truth of Christ, not the value Christ had for him.
Doug's question was sophisticated in the way of the medieval question of whether or not God could make a rock so heavy that He could not lift it. Doug was asking this: If one is tolerant in one's religious assertions, then one is clandestinely understanding these assertions as not have truth-conditions. But why be committed to the assertion of a particular body of statements or the doing of a set of actions if there are no truth-conditions grounding the assertion of the statements or the doing of the actions? Alternately, if one is committed to a set of assertions or a class of actions, then one is presupposing their truth, but if this is so then why be deeply tolerant of unjustified views at odds with those that one has good reason to regard as true? Just as the property of making a rock so heavy that God can't lift it cannot properly be applied to God, so to the property of being deeply tolerant of contrary religious claims while be profoundly committed to one's own cannot properly be applied to late twentieth-century Christian believers, those no longer believing as did the Founding Fathers that tolerance pertains to epistemic humility with regard to the domain of religious fact.
Dominant strands of Lutheran theology over the past 200 years have tended to downplay the idea that there exists a realm of theological facts independent of human awareness, perception, conception and language. Kantian assumptions within theology departments at German universities undercut notions of divine substantiality and causality. As European Lutheran theology hit American shores (particularly after World War II), and comingled with American assumptions about the fact/value distinction, a Lutheran theological ethos emerged that was disdainful of Lutheran Orthodoxy, particularly it's penchant to regard confessional and doctrinal statements as affirmations of theological fact. The result was heightened tensions among Lutherans, a tension pertaining to both semantics and ontology.
While conservative traditions like the Missouri and Wisconsin Synods continued to assume that there was some objective fact of the matter about which confessional and doctrinal statements were speaking truly, the precursor church bodies which became the ELCA began leaning towards an understanding of such language that connected more to human experience. While the former thus understood tolerance as grounded in epistemic limitation, the latter came to see it as an affirmation of the particularity of the believer's cultural existence itself. Tensions ran high, and it did not help when spokesman of the former sometimes suggested that the tolerance of epistemic humility was due to a willful abandonment of the objectivity of revelation. Nor were tensions abated when the latter seemed to think that confessional and doctrinal affirmations somehow denied the authenticity of the theologian or preacher's voice, and that such affirmations simply strangled the believer's authentic religious life and practice.
The Institute of Lutheran Theology emerged, in part, because it became time for there to be an institution that was both deeply sympathetic to the starting points of the various Lutheran traditions, and that understood these starting points within the broader historical and philosophical context. It is time now that Lutherans talk seriously to each other. It is time we think together the dialectic of tolerance and commitment, time we ask together how an affirmation of both is possible. In so asking, we shall undoubtedly learn a great deal more about ourselves. Such learning is a very good thing, for it is time that we dialogue with each other in a spirit of tolerance and commitment, a spirit that shall take the truth claims of all partners seriously, while adjudicating conflicting truth claims within an ethos of epistemic humility.
Sunday, June 12, 2016
Propositional Content, Truth-Conditions and Existential Empowerment
For a very long time I have puzzled over the relationship within theology among the notions of syntax, semantics and existential empowerment. A proposition is uttered and has meaning. A person hears it and orients himself in a different direction in the hearing. The pastor utters, "Christ is risen." The parishioner hears the assertion and is seemingly empowered by it: She feels otherwise than she likely would have felt, thinks otherwise than she likely would have thought, and behaves differently than she otherwise would have behaved. While all this seems clear, it is not. In this brief article, I want to reflect upon this unclarity.
Preachers proclaiming the Word of God to hearers say such things as, "You are forgiven," "Christ died for you," "God hears your prayers," "God knows everything in your heart," "God demands that you help the poor," "God wants you to love your neighbor even as Christ has loved you," "The Holy Spirit in you is praying through you," and "God's gracious love makes all things new." Obviously, in the course of any sermon, a preacher utters many statements like these. As you look closely at them, it is clear that many really do prima facie have the form of statements; they seem to be claims about God, God's will for us, and God's gracious love of us.
If such statements were made in the presence of philosophers, there might erupt a discussion as to the truth-conditions (or lack of the same) of such statements. What makes true the statements, 'Christ died for you', or 'God's gracious love makes all things new'? What precisely must be the case for the statement 'Christ died for you' to be asserted as true? Is it made true by the psychological properties of the utterer? Is it made true by some set of events, entities, properties or states of affairs, the presence of which determines the statement's truth and the absence of which determines its falsity?
Or is the statement not true at all? Perhaps it is a saying of the group that one must say to be part of a group. Or perhaps it is merely an expression of one's own subjectivity, one's feelings and existential orientations. Maybe the statements are really not statements at all, but rather pseudo-statements masquerading as statements with truth values. Without a truth-value, a sentence cannot be a statement, it cannot state rightly or wrongly what is in fact the case. It can, of course, be language that is nonetheless doing something. For instance, it might make a promise or a command, express a feeling or hope, or give thanks or praise. But without a truth-value, the statement cannot in principle make a claim rightly or wrongly about the way that things are.
Theologians, particularly Lutheran theologians, have recently displayed a penchant for disparaging ontology. ('Recent' here connotes the last 225 years or so.) They seemingly assume that the discipline having to do with being is not a discipline properly relatable to theology, the discipline having to do with logos or Word. Perhaps they believe, or are somewhere on the trajectory of believing, with the Neo-Kantians that while the categories of 'being' and 'cause' are appropriate for die Natur, they are out of place in the realm of der Geist (spirit), the region pertaining to 'value'. Accordingly, theological ontology is misguided because it is an investigation which would locate God in an inappropriate region. God would be, at best, a being among other beings -- albeit the highest of those beings. But how could a being among beings be a being that fulfills the primal condition of God being God: the condition that God is infinitely qualitative different than creation, that God is totaliter aliter than all that is?
Maybe they simply think that ontology is metaphysics and that interest in metaphysics is symptomatic of a theology of glory. Instead of God revealing Himself in weakness and vulnerability on the Cross, human beings search for God on the basis of the created order, locating God at the apex of truth, goodness and beauty. But is not such a metaphysical inquiry an attempt to build a bridge to the infinite by standing in the finite? Is not that attempt a proud seeking after the glory of God in strength and impassibility? "We must search for God where is revealed," they say, "We must find it in is in His Word, not search to unmask the hidden God!"
But these ways of thinking are simply confusions, most often perpetrated by those who have imperfect understandings of what ontology is and does. Ontology is concerned with truth-conditions, with those conditions that must obtain to make true those statements we regard as such. Whatever events, objects, properties and states of affairs which make such statements true are precisely those events, object, properties and states of affairs we hold exist. Simply put, all of our statement utterings have ontological commitments. Just as some state of affairs makes true the statement 'the cat is on the mat' -- presumably the existence of a cat, a mat, and a particular dyadic relation of "onto" such that the cat is onto the mat -- so some state of affairs would make true the statements 'Christ is resurrected from the dead', and 'Because Christ lives, you shall live also'. But what might these be?
Now enters the traditional problem of religious language. What exactly does 'Christ lives' mean and what would 'I live' mean in its wake? Clearly, we know what it is for something to live. A being lives if it fulfills certain biological conditions. But would Christ's living fulfill those conditions? Perhaps, if we are thinking about Christ's living alongside Peter's living. But is the Christ who lives alongside Paul's living a Christ who lives in the same way that Christ lived alongside of Peter's living? What would a post-resurrected living be? A fortiori what would a post-Ascension living entail? Would a human living that is not a biological living be a living? Perhaps one says, "yes," but it is not altogether clear what one is saying when saying it.
Everything I have said so far connects to the problem of the assertion of propositional content and the effect of such asserting on existential empowerment. Pastor Roy goes to see parishioner Mary who has been battling cancer, and now appears to be rapidly losing the battle. The doctors say she may have only weeks to live. Pastor Roy says to Mary that death has not ultimate victory over her because Christ has conquered death and through His resurrection, she will be resurrected as well. Mary thinks about this a moment and says, "Pastor, is that true, or are you just saying that to make me feel better." Pastor Roy considers her statement and replies, "It is true, Mary, you will be resurrected with Christ." Mary, always the skeptic, follows up, "But in what sense will I be resurrected? Will I have a body and will I know myself to be the same person I was before I died?" Pastor Roy deliberates a moment and then hazards the following: "Mary, I don't know if you will have a body that is like the body you now have, nor a psychology like that which you now have, I just know that you will be resurrected." Mary is silent a moment and then returns to her original statement, "Pastor, is that true, or are you just saying that to make me feel better?"
Mary is concerned with the semantics of Pastor Roy's assertions. What do the statements he is proclaiming mean, and are they true? To know if they are true it seems, she must know what they mean. But Mary knows that locating meaning logically prior to truth cannot ultimately explain what it is that 'meaning' means. Mary grasps that for a statement to mean x rather than y, one must know the conditions under which x is true and y not. Whatever these truth-conditions are, are what makes an assertion's meaning mean. She knows that when Pastor Roy says to her, "Death does not have ultimate victory over you because Christ has conquered death and through His resurrection, you will be resurrected as well," it makes all the difference in the world to the assertion's meaning what must obtain in order for the sentence to be true. What makes true Christ's conquering death and being resurrected such that she will be resurrected as well? Moreover, is it not clear that whatever makes that true makes all the difference in the world as to how she feels, thinks and behaves in the hearing, over and against how she otherwise would have felt, thought and behaved?
A theological statement's semantics, its truth-conditions and truth, is intimately related to its ability to existentially empower. What I am saying is that it makes a deep existential difference to most people in the face of impending death what it is about which they might legitimately hope. But is this not merely a baseless assertion? Why think that Mary's empowerment in the face of death depends upon some fact of the matter about Christ's life after death? Is not the Word enough? Is not the proclamation of the Word enough to empower? Why get into semantics and philosophical discussion when none is clearly needed?
But it is clearly needed; this is the point. The mere uttering of words cannot empowerment produce. But is not the Word external? Is that not enough? It is only enough, I would say, if one were Zoroastrian and had to have all of the words right in order to produce the correct result. It is enough only if one believes that words are magical bringing about effects without means. Lutherans believe in the real presence, after all. For the external Word to be really present demands that the Word appear in, under, around and beyond the words which bear it. But in order for the Word to be present, it must mean. Without meaning the Word remains in bare externality; it remains incapable of connection to fallen structures in need of salvation. Blessed are they that know their need of God.
What I am suggesting is that a mature Lutheran theology of the Word can indeed connect to truth-conditions. They are the means by which our hopes are fanned and fears quelled. While the argument is difficult, is it not self-evident that Mary's fears about death and her hopes for a future beyond it are linked inextricably to what she thinks really is the case with regards to these things? The Holy Spirit is carried by the Word and is ever related to the Word, and the Holy Spirit works through means. Is not the Spirit's ability to deliver the Word through human words related to the empowerment of the hearer of the Word, an empowerment that depends upon the hearer knowing the meaning and truth of what is said? Perhaps one might even say the Spirit forms the link between the proclamation of words, and the Wording of the Word in the salvation of its hearer.
So Mary went out and listened to the voice of Pastor Roy and her spirit was calmed, for Pastor Roy spoke a truth that she could not invent. To have understood Roy in the flesh would have meant that she understand his remarks figuratively, for denizens of nature can only speak the spirit as an as if. But because of God's Spirit she did not need to spiritualize the brutal facts of nature. Because of His Spirit, she knew in her spirit that Nature was a far bigger thing than ever she had realized.
Labels:
existential empowerment,
semantic realism,
semantics,
truth
Thursday, September 27, 2012
Thinking Truth Non-Propositionally
"I am the Way and the Truth and the Life."
I regard the statement as true. As such, it is a propositional truth. Precisely how a statement is a propositional truth is a matter of considerable debate, of course. Some say it is true because regarding it so issues in desirable effects. "Truth is what works," declares the confident pragmatist.
Others say it is true because it coheres appropriately with a wider class of statements. It is consistent with them, and it, and the wider class of statements, mutually presuppose each other so that there are no arbitrary and disconnected statements from which the statement is deducible. Getting clear on the coherence theory of truth is never easy because it is not perspicuous what the precise boundaries of coherence are.
Many say that the statement is propositionally true because it appropriately states what is the case. Getting precision on what is the case apart from the statement, and what the appropriate way is in which the statement and the extra-linguistic states of affairs relate, is not altogether facile. What constitutes the criterion by which to adjudicate when a statement appropriately states the case? If there is an isomorphism between statement and the reality it depicts? If so, what are the relata of the relations isomorphically obtaining?
In the absence of clear criteria which unfailingly picks out the truth of a putative propositional truth, some claim that the truth of propositional truth is primitive. One need not have some elaborate theory of meaning which, when appropriately satisfied, delivers truth. One could start with truth and discern that meaning in some way is derivative upon that.
Whatever be one's theory, the notion that truth is propositional is standard fare in philosophical thinking. A philosopher can give alternative accounts of how the truth of "I am the Way and the Truth and the Life" is true. This much is certain. But the philosopher runs into a brick wall when trying to think the content of the proposition in which utterer is identified with Truth itself. What could this mean? How could truth be non-propositional? How can truth be non-linguistic? What does it mean to say that 'Jesus' is 'Truth'?
One might at this point say that 'truth' just means 'reality', and that Jesus is thus 'real'. But this way of proceeding is fraught with much difficulty because to say 'Jesus is Truth' is clearly intended to say more than 'Jesus is real', for one would quite glibly say 'the ball is real', but never aver 'the ball is truth'.
There are two more promising steps forward, one Hegelian and one Heideggerian. Hegel famously claimed, "Diese Gegenstaende sind wahr, wenn sie das sind, was sie sein sollen, d.h. wenn ihre Realitaet ihrem Begriff entspricht" ("Objects are true if they are as they ought to be, that is, when their reality corresponds to their notion."). [Enzyklopaedie, Wissenschaft der Logik (1830), 213, n. 127] Accordingly, Jesus is 'truth' in that he corresponds fully to the concept of what it is to be the God-man. But is this "correspondence" really non-propositional? Think what it would be to specify how a thing corresponds without using concepts expressible in language. How could one thing not be another thing in the absence of that which differentiates? And how can that which differentiates not finally be expressible in language?
Another way forward is Heideggerian. Famously Heidegger argued that alethia (truth) is a unconcealing (Unverborgenheit) or as an Entbergung or "unveiling." Early on Heidegger found the phenomenon of unveiling as the ontological ground for the possibility of truth. However, later Heidegger admitted that die Frage nach der Unverborgenheit als solcher ist nicht die Frage nach die Wahrheit. (Maybe he realized that if truth needed an ontological ground in unconcealing, falsity needed one in concealing.) Whatever might be thought of Heidegger's turn away from truth as unconcealing in his Das Ende der Philosophie und die Aufgabe des Denkens, he remained convinced that truth had something to do with correctness, and that correctness had everything to do with unveiling. But how can one claim that the experience of unveiling ontologically grounds truth when this experience could as easily be described as truth's effect?
Given what has been said, how is it unquestionably possible for Jesus to be 'the Truth'? Moreover, if Jesus is identified with God's self-revelation, then how can that revelation be true? The standard move here is to distinguish between the objective, historical process of revelation and the subjective interpretation of that revelation. (One might claim a la Pannenberg that a distinction holds between the "outer revelation" and the "inspiration" as the interpretation of these events in the Biblical witnesses.) While the first is putatively non-propositional, the second is not. But what is it to be a manifestation of God in and through historical events, that is, in and through particular things? Furthermore, how could such a manifestation be non-linguistic? If Stacia is a "true friend," but Bob is not, then what is it about Stacia that distinguishes her over and against Bob; what is that "it" that is not in principle capturable by language?
Twentieth century theology, in its effort to escape the "propositional theory of truth" with respect to divine revelation - - the generally-regarded spurious claim that divine revelation is an impartation of information -- seems to lurch into a semantic crevasse of vanquished lucidity. Simply put, one does not know what one is talking about when discoursing about a revelation that is in principle non-propositional. That God was in Christ reconciling the world to Himself could, after all, be true, but what is true is the fact that God was in Christ reconciling the world to Himself. A revelation that cannot be expressed as fact is finally too amorphous to be revelatory; such a revelation is ultimately a night in which all cows are black.
Labels:
Hegel,
Heidegger,
Lutheran Theology,
revelation,
truth
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)