I am baffled by the tendency I find in theology to place “theological depth” in inverse relationship to rational clarity, consistency and coherency. This surely is not the case in other disciplines. For example, to get deeply into set theory only increases clarity, consistency and coherency. The same is true in chemistry. But, lamentably, it is clearly and consistently not true in theology.
I received an e-mail the other day that displays this theological malady of avoiding precision. The writer was taking issue with something I had written about God. I had said that God’s hiddenness does not entail the rejection of theological realism, semantic realism about God-talk, and the possibility of theophysical causation. In making my point, I had used Luther’s explanation in the Small Catechism to the first article of the Apostle’s Creed. Luther writes, “I believe that God has created me and all creatures, that he has given me my body . . . “ My point was simply that Luther presupposed a causal connection between God and the universe.
The e-mail said a rather curious thing. It claims that one ought to read the First Article in light of what it says about human beings, not what it says about God. The e-mail further suggests, I believe, that to make claims about God places human beings in a post-Enlightenment arena where we stand as neutral observers judging God.
I find this all very puzzling. Why are we Lutherans so convinced that we violate the First Commandment when we say anything about God? Of course, I agree that any attempt to map divine ontology is decidedly un-Lutheran. But this is not done, I think, when we say that God’s creating the world entails that God causes the world to be. Logically, saying that human beings have certain properties with respect to the divine entails that the divine has certain properties with respect to us.
Take the following statements:
1) Bob is a creature
2) God created Bob
Many Lutherans want to see (1) and (2) as making quite different statements. While (1) ascribes the monadic property to Bob of being a creature, (2) says that God has a relational property of causing Bob to be. (1) seems true because of deep Lutheran insights about existential-phenomenological-ontological “placedness,” that is, it is true on the basis of human experience. (2), however, seems to be a metaphysical statement about God that is wholly out of place within the Lutheran context. Many Lutherans want to regard (1) as somehow expressing the existentiality of the self, and (2) as declaring a daring metaphysical theophysical causation. (1) is thus admitted, and (2) denied.
But all of this is conceptual confusion. Take the word ‘creature’. If we are to employ the word in a way consistent with its original meaning, it entails ‘being created’. While we can, of course, change the word into meaning something else, the fact remains that the term is likethe word 'creation' in being related to that which creates. Logically, there can be no creation without a creator. In a similar way, there can be no creature without a creator. To use the word ‘creation’ to apply to things not having been created is to violate the ordinary way in which we use words. Similarly, to use ‘creature’ in such a way as not to entail ‘being created’ is to violate the ordinary usage of these terms.
In reality, (1) can be parsed as ‘Bob is one having been created.’ Since, of course, one cannot be created without there being one to create you, (1) becomes ‘Bob is created by a creator’. Since we identify the creator as God, (1) reads ‘Bob is created by God’. Now, it should be easy to see that (1) and (2) are logically equivalent. I can conceive of no possible world where Bob is created by God, and God does not create Bob, or alternately, where God creates Bob, but Bob is not created by God. In truth, (1) and (2) share the same logical form; they state the same putative fact: ‘There is Bob and God, such that God and Bob are members of the set of all ordered pairs such that the first member creates the second’. (This is the standard extensional understanding of ‘God creates Bob’.)
Now one can object, of course, claiming that one does not mean by ‘Bob is a creature’ the proposition 'he is created by God'. But if this be so, then why use the word ‘creature’? Why not use another word, a word that more precisely states what is being asserted? If the word ‘creature’ is to be applied if and only if certain existential-phenomenological conditions are met, then why not eliminate the term in favor of a precise specification of those underlying existential-phenomenological conditions? This would be far clearer for all involved, and it would avoid useless ambiguity.
Lutheran theology can be precise. The problem is that in order to escape the ontological problems posed by the Enlightenment, Lutheran theology moved to become “deeper” so that its language no longer connoted what the average pewsitter presupposed. It is all a bit disingenuous and, I believe, it is time to come clean.
Dennis Bielfeldt
Dr. Bielfedt,
ReplyDeleteI just wanted to know that I've just finished reading all your posts and find this blog very interesting. I've read alot of your stuff also on the Wordalone website and have also enjoyed that.
I was talking with Dr. Mickey Mattox a few months ago (I'm a doctoral candidate in Systematic Theology at Marquette) and he said that you were working on a project regarding Luther's ontology. I love for you to do a post on that.
I'd also be interested to hear some thoughts about debate between Scotus and Aquinas on the univocity of being. Luther in my thinking seems to transcend both categories because he believes that God's reality is fundamentally hidden, yet on the other hand can be spoken about in univocal terms in his acts. That is, there is nothing particularly analogical when I say that God has forgiven me or condemns me with the law. In proclamation God literally becomes love for me, as he was literally wrath before and apart from it. Similarly, there's nothing analogical about saying that God made the world. On the other hand, God in himself remains hidden, God's act is not identical with his being, since his acts are different depending on where I encounter him (hidden God vs. revealed God). So then, what does one do with traditional Trinitarian language? Do I mean that the Father literally begat the Son, or is this simply analogical way of talking about the divine life? If the later is true, then we have to bring back analogy, which in my opinion seems always without fail to lead us back to a theology of glory (whether it's Barth or Aquinas doing it!).
Jack,
ReplyDeleteYes, I shall post something on Luther and ontology.
You write some very interesting things about Luther and his take on the question of the univocity of being. I'll try to put something together on that as well. I understand, of course, there is putative deep signifance, for Lutherans, in saying such things as "his acts are different depending on where I encounter him." After all, was it not Luther who said, "credere macht Gott?"
However, if we find no counterpoise to these textual moments in Luther, we should ultimately have to relegate him to the anti-realist camp, something I don't think any good nominalist could facilely endure.
I appreciate you taking a look at this blog, Jack. (I am usually not so tardy in my responses.) Hopefully, we shall have much to talk about.
Dennis
Thanks, I look forward to more posts and more dialogue.
ReplyDeleteIt's always an adventure to retroject things back into Luther's head, but I'm adventurous. Luther would say it is breaking the 1st commandment if you don't take the 1st Article of the Apostle's Creed as referring to the divine power of creation and causation, and instead take it as a reference to human beings. A God who couldn't create or cause would be unworthy of our worship. Since death and resurrection are the severe remedy for sin for the God of the Bible, to remove those attributes would be to remove the basis for any trust. Why would you trust a being who couldn't do anything to overcome the problems of evil, sin, and non-being.
ReplyDeleteInverting the meaning of the 1st Article to speak of human life rather than divine properties is remaking God into ones' own image, which would qualify as idolatry and a concomitant violation of the 1st Commandment in Luther's mind
Of course many Lutheran pastors could care less about what Luther would say to this strange inversion of the 1st article . One wonders why they claim the tile Lutheran for themselves, but that leads to a discussion of intellectual honesty and integrity among ELCA clergy types. A future discussion maybe.
Mark,
ReplyDeleteIt is interesting how particular theological starting points place stress other theological loci. Take, for instance, the injunction to always "start with Christ" and "derive what we can say of God from our encounter with Christ." This starting point can, given the right conditions, eventuate in a theology where there is no divine realm at all. One just makes certain existential-phenomenological assumptions. Accordingly, creation becomes a symbol upon the horizon of human being. The point is this: all action is ultimately human action because there is no way to get out of the phenomenological net and "build a bridge" to what lies outside. But, of course, "what lies outside" has always been of critical importance to Christian theology. One might argue that the attempt to provide meaning for theological language through an existential-phenomenological ontology is itself a triumph, of sorts, for Feuerbach. (But if one assumes there is no other game, then this game might be better than none at all.)
Dennis
Mark,
ReplyDeleteIt is interesting how particular theological starting points place stress other theological loci. Take, for instance, the injunction to always "start with Christ" and "derive what we can say of God from our encounter with Christ." This starting point can, given the right conditions, eventuate in a theology where there is no divine realm at all. One just makes certain existential-phenomenological assumptions. Accordingly, creation becomes a symbol upon the horizon of human being. The point is this: all action is ultimately human action because there is no way to get out of the phenomenological net and "build a bridge" to what lies outside. But, of course, "what lies outside" has always been of critical importance to Christian theology. One might argue that the attempt to provide meaning for theological language through an existential-phenomenological ontology is itself a triumph, of sorts, for Feuerbach. (But if one assumes there is no other game, then this game might be better than none at all.)
Dennis